Observable signatures of the quantum nature of gravity at low energies have recently emerged as a promising new research field. One prominent avenue is to test for gravitationally induced entanglement between two mesoscopic masses prepared in spatial superposition. Here, we analyze such proposals and what one can infer from them about the quantum nature of gravity as well as the electromagnetic analogues of such tests. We show that it is not possible to draw conclusions about mediators: even within relativistic physics, entanglement generation can equally be described in terms of mediators or in terms of non-local processes—relativity does not dictate a local channel. Such indirect tests, therefore, have limited ability to probe the nature of the process establishing the entanglement as their interpretation is inherently ambiguous. We also show that cosmological observations already demonstrate some aspects of quantization that these proposals aim to test. Nevertheless, the proposed experiments would probe how gravity is sourced by spatial superpositions of matter, an untested new regime of quantum physics.
I. INTRODUCTION
Quantum gravity remains one of the main challenges of modern physics. Many promising theoretical avenues are being pursued,1,2 but to date, no complete theory of quantum gravity is known. An alternative route has been proposed by Penrose3,4 and others,5–7 in which quantum mechanical unitarity breaks down at sufficiently large mass scales. Such proposals have ushered in the exciting new field of experimental searches for quantum gravity at low energies, as they provide distinct signatures that can be observed if sufficiently large systems can be controlled and prepared in quantum superpositions.8–11 These proposals and the rapid progress in quantum control of larger and larger systems12,13 have sparked an interest in experimental signatures of the interface between quantum mechanics and gravity at low energies both in terms of testing speculative new models3–7,14–17 and expected new signatures from gravitational and quantum physics as we know them.18–21 To date, no experiment exists that either proves any of the new physics or the quantum nature of gravitational degrees of freedom, and it also seems that Gedanken experiments in support of quantization are inconclusive.22–25 Thus, any experimental signature that would suggest the quantum nature of gravity would be of extreme interest and shed light on uncharted territory.
One promising experimental avenue that aims to infer the quantum nature of gravity is based on creating gravitationally induced entanglement between two source masses26,27 (GIE).28 In this variation of the well-known Colella–Overhauser–Werner setup,29 two matter-wave interferometers are placed very close to each other (see Fig. 1). The two interferometers create the superposition states and , respectively, each of size and their centers a distance d apart. If the matter waves are sufficiently heavy, they will source observable gravitational effects themselves, and the Newtonian interaction will generate entanglement between the two systems. After time t, the state becomes . The two relative phases are induced by the Newtonian interaction and are given by . In this idealized case (neglecting noise), the state is entangled for any phases , and maximally entangled for , which can be measured through an entanglement witness.26,30–32 The authors of Refs. 26 and 27 argue that this entanglement generation is an indirect witness of the quantization of gravity. The essence of the argument is that the interaction is not instantaneous as suggested by the Newtonian description, but mediated by some local degrees of freedom, and since entanglement cannot be generated by local operations and classical communication (LOCC),33,34 these degrees of freedom have to be quantized. Since the original proposals, several variations of this concept have been put forward.35–44 However, the very question if such proposals can test the quantum nature of gravity has remained open for debate. Some have argued against it,45–47 while others put arguments forward in favor.24,37,48–52 The main argument in favor of inferring the quantum nature of the mediating gravitational field stems from the quantum information perspective that limits entanglement generation from LOCC and the assumption that the interaction is induced by local mediators. In contrast, the major argument against the inference of quantum gravity is the use of the Newtonian limit in which the interaction is mediated non-locally.
Here, we clarify what conclusions one can draw from the experiment by critically exploring the assumptions that go into it. By definition, if entanglement is observed in the experiment, then this demonstrates a non-LOCC type channel. This alone is, of course, of great interest. Nevertheless, the open question around these proposals—and what we address in this work—is if one can learn more about the nature of the underlying system that mediates entanglement, namely, of the gravitational field. As we will show below, the question remains ambiguous and depends on what prior assumptions one takes for granted—in some cases, even what metaphysical view one prefers. We show that while inferring the existence of gravitons is reasonable if one assumes the validity of the relativistic field theory, this interpretation is not unique. It relies on the assumption of local mediators for entanglement, which in relativity are not the physical gravitons for this case, but particles that are otherwise unmeasurable. Moreover, models with inherent non-locality can reproduce the entanglement without the existence of any mediators. Importantly, while the term locality is often interchangeably used with the relativistic notion of Lorentz invariance, it needs not be: even within relativistic physics as we know it, entanglement generation can be described non-locally by eliminating redundant gauge degrees of freedom. More generally, a fully non-local interpretation exists—the Wheeler–Feynman (WF) absorber formulation.53–57 When applied to quantized charges,58–65 it reproduces all physical predictions of Quantum Electrodynamics (QED) including entanglement, but the theory does not contain quantized, local degrees of freedom that create the entanglement. If such an absorber theory can be formulated for gravity, it would explain gravitationally induced entanglement without introducing gravitons, while still being consistent with classical general relativity. With a viable non-local explanation for the generation of entanglement, its observation alone is, therefore, insufficient to infer the existence of quantized mediators. However, in contrast to the electromagnetic case, it remains an open question if an absorber-type formulation exists for full general relativity although it exists in the relativistic weak field limit. Regardless of the question how entanglement is mediated, the experiment involves superpositions of source masses. As such, observation of entanglement, thus, supports the view that gravitational fields are sourced coherently by a superposition of sources, if quantum physics is not modified. This is independent of the question of what mediates entanglement and does not rely on the LOCC argument. The experiment, if successful, would prove this superposition of Newtonian fields, without the above-mentioned ambiguities, as also highlighted in Refs. 50 and 51. Nonetheless, we argue that it can already be inferred from cosmological observations that quantum states coherently source Newtonian fields.
In this manuscript, we explore systematically what conclusions one can draw from a GIE experiment, depending on what prior assumptions one takes for granted. Our work is structured as follows: in Sec. II, we discuss the most conservative case, the Newtonian limit without any additional assumptions. In Sec. III, we focus on QED as an analogous case and show that the conclusions are ambiguous and depend on (equivalent) formulations of the field theory. Section IV discusses the case of relativistic weak-field quantum gravity relevant to the GIE experiment. Section V revisits all previously discussed formulations from the perspective of path integral quantization, providing a unified picture. We focus in Sec. VI on cosmology and show that current observations already give evidence of quantum weak-field gravity as in the GIE proposal. Our discussion in Sec. VII gives a brief comparison to other works and provides an overview of the different interpretations and conclusions that one can draw from GIE.
II. NON-RELATIVISTIC CASE
We first focus on the physics in the non-relativistic limit, which is entirely sufficient to explain the setup. At this level, there is no assumption of any underlying field theory or additional ontology. It is the minimal interpretation, as no additional assumptions about the underlying physics beyond what is experimentally measured have to be imposed.
In the non-relativistic limit, there is a direct analogy between the Newtonian gravitational interaction and the electrostatic Coulomb law. To clarify the relevant physics, we briefly review how these enter the quantum theory of non-relativistic particles. This will highlight the non-locality of the non-relativistic theory, and to what extent one can say that the Coulomb and Newtonian potentials “are quantized.”
The novelty of the GIE experiment is, thus, that the Newtonian field as in Eq. (6) has to be treated quantum mechanically and cannot be approximated by a mean field description. The sources for gravity are themselves in superposition. While this regime of physics has never been directly tested, the predictions assume regular quantum mechanics (2). The gravitationally active density is in a spatial superposition, and, thus, the operator nature of the potential cannot be neglected. However, nothing in this description involves mediators, and, thus, nothing can be said whether gravitons are quantized at this level of the description. Such claims rely on extra assumptions, such as the assumption that is the component of a more fundamental relativistic quantum field that has local degrees of freedom.
Sections III and IV will answer under which conditions/assumptions our quantized Newtonian potential also implies the existence of quantized gravitons and deals with questions of non-locality using the simpler but very analogous example of electromagnetism (summarized in Table I).
Formulation of interaction . | Equation . | LOCC? . |
---|---|---|
Non-relativistic Coulomb | (1) | |
QED (Lorentz gauge) | (9) | |
QED (Coulomb gauge) | (17) | |
QED (absorber, no EM field) | (23) |
III. ELECTROMAGNETIC FIELD THEORY
We now proceed to analyze possible conclusions beyond the Newtonian limit, under the assumption that one takes relativistic field theory for granted. Again, we note that the non-relativistic limit is sufficient to describe the experiment as in Sec. II. Now, however, we take the view that from other experiments and established physics, we can additionally assume that there is an underlying field theory that mediates the entanglement, even if it is not directly probed in the experiment. The question is, can one conclude something more than what has been established in Sec. II?
To simplify the discussion and gain intuition, we will assume that the entanglement production in a GIE-like experiment is solely due to electric charge (thus technically it is electromagnetically induced entanglement), before discussing the case of gravity in Sec. IV. Our discussion within this section is then guaranteed to be based on established physics. Our task is, thus, to find out what we would learn about the quantum nature of electromagnetism in the hypothetical scenario where we only had the electromagnetic analogue of the GIE experiment at our disposal. In particular, we investigate which assumptions about electromagnetism are needed to infer the existence of (quantized) photons from witnessing entanglement from this experiment alone.
In this section, we, therefore, slightly modify the experiment shown in Fig. 1 and assume that two objects that are put into superposition have electric charge q with and interact via the Coulomb potential .
A. Local mediators: Lorentz invariant formulation of QED
Note that in (9b), the term that corresponds to scalar photons comes with a minus sign. Quantization of QED in Lorentz gauge requires the use of the so-called indefinite Hilbert space metric.68 A pedagogical presentation of the method can be found in Ref. 70.
The state (14) corresponds to an entangled state of the two oscillators (A, B) for . It is crucial that in (16), apart from summing over intermediate oscillator states, there is a summation over intermediate photon states . In a recent work, a similar computation was performed for the gravitational case, but the summation over intermediate oscillator states has been omitted.74 Thus, we conclude that in this picture, the intermediate photons establish the entanglement between the two oscillators. In the near field regime in which the transverse photons do not contribute, the oscillators get entangled due to the exchange of scalar and longitudinal photons—mediators that cannot be directly observed.
When using a local gauge such as the Lorentz gauge as the underlying ontology, the LOCC argument, therefore, implies that entanglement is created by quantized mediators, since locality is pre-assumed and, thus, classicality of the channel cannot hold if entanglement is generated. The process is a particular combination of the scalar and longitudinal photons and does not directly reveal the quantum nature of transverse (physical) photons. If QED was not pre-assumed, but instead, we attempted to infer the quantum nature of the electromagnetic field from the GIE experiment and the LOCC argument, we would still not be able to directly infer quantization of physically measurable mediators. However, consistency with Lorentz invariance and locality of the quantum fields will then also require these transverse degrees of freedom to exist and be quantized. This is a matter of theoretical consistency, but not something that can be directly inferred from the entanglement experiment, even in this picture. The experiment is not sensitive to actual physical mediators—photons (or gravitons in the GIE case)—and entanglement is created by other local mediators that can never be directly observed. Nevertheless, LOCC then implies that these must be quantized.
B. No mediators: QED in Coulomb gauge
The Hilbert space of the whole system (particles + EM field) is , where is the state space of the particles in which and act and corresponds to the state space of the photon-radiation field in which and act. Note that predominantly the third term in (17) generates the direct interaction between the two non-relativistic and quasi-static systems, and it is fundamentally non-local. Since radiation (retardation effects) is not important in the GIE experiment, one has, thus, to conclude that, in the formulation of QED in the Coulomb gauge, the entanglement between the charges is established non-locally, via the Coulomb term (as also pointed out in Ref. 45). In this case, the LOCC argument alone to prove that the underlying process that generates entanglement is itself a quantum system does not apply, and nothing about the mediators can be inferred. For further details regarding QED in Coulomb gauge, the reader is referred to Subsection 1 of the Appendix.
In fact, all interactions of the standard model and gravity are gauge theories, and, thus, if the formulation of these theories is restricted to involve only the dynamics of the physical degrees of freedom, all these theories are non-local (in that the Lagrangian density is not a sum of local products of operators). Only with the help of auxiliary gauge, degrees of freedom are these theories local. It, thus, is a matter of taste if locality is pre-assumed or not, and, thus, whether the LOCC argument implies the existence of quantum mediators or not.
C. No mediators: QED as absorber theory
Above we discussed different interpretations of the experiment based on choosing different gauges. This ambiguity was also pointed out in Ref. 45. It shows that the notion of local mediators is not necessary to explain the experiment, and, thus, no conclusion about its quantization can be drawn (see also Table I).
In particular, Feynman suggested in 194879 that one can replace (7) with (23a) for any QED process, which contains no external, real photons, without any change in the experimental results. According to this theorem (see Ref. 60 for a proof), one can eliminate all virtual photons from the mathematical description of the QED processes. This theorem directly applies to the EM analogue of the GIE proposal in which on-shell photons are not involved.80
While the physical predictions are the same, the interpretation of such a theory is different. In this action-at-a-distance formulation, the electromagnetic field does not exist, and particles interact directly, without mediators, on the lightcone, see (23a). Such an ontology in the context of the GIE experiment has profound consequences: since the direct interaction on the lightcone is non-local in space, the LOCC argument does not imply a quantized mediating system for entanglement. This means that witnessing entanglement in the electromagnetic version of the GIE experiment could not unambiguously tell us if the electromagnetic field needs to be quantized. Thus, entanglement alone only proves source mass quantization, since there is an experimentally equivalent alternative formulation, where no mediators are involved in producing the entanglement.
In conclusion, the electromagnetic analogue of the GIE experiment would tell us nothing about mediators beyond our prior believes about which formulation of electromagnetism is more likely to be true. One either believes that physics is local which means first that longitudinal and scalar photons establish the entanglement—and not the physical transverse photons and second that transverse photons must exist and be quantized as well, since only the combination of these three types of photons can build a local field theory. Or one does not manually exclude non-local establishment of entanglement, which is the case in the Coulomb formulation of QED. Alternatively, in an absorber framework, only the sources are real, and the entire electromagnetic field is a mathematical fiction and should not be quantized. The entanglement in this picture does not stem from mediators but from the charges interacting non-locally. All formulations, however, yield the exact same experimental outcomes. It is important to note that the case of (where locality does not hold, see Table I) does not necessarily imply a classical channel. It simply means that a local quantum channel is not necessary to produce the entanglement. In the case of non-local formulations of QED, entanglement is produced through a quantum channel, which can be directly inferred from the Hamiltonian (17) or Lagrangian (23). However, in the case of Coulomb gauge or absorber theory, that quantum channel is not a mediating degree of freedom but a non-local interaction between the charges.
D. Locality versus causality
As we have discussed above, locality is not a necessary condition even in a relativistic theory. One is free to choose a local and manifestly covariant formulation of QED, but a non-local description is also always possible. Nevertheless, causality is preserved in all of the formulations. There is, thus, a fundamental difference between non-locality and causality, and only the latter is fundamentally required by Lorentz invariance.
In the Coulomb gauge, despite the various non-local (instantaneous) pieces that appear in (17), only causal physical processes are described.81,82 In particular, it was shown in Refs. 82 and 83 that, in Coulomb gauge, the instantaneous Coulomb potential cancels exactly the instantaneous piece that appears in the vector field to give rise to causal (retarded) EM fields, the so-called Jefimenko fields.84
From a quantum field theory point of view, the photon propagator contains a piece that violates Lorentz invariance. This term in the propagator exactly cancels the acausal, Lorentz violating Coulomb potential that appears in the Hamiltonian (17), to give a perfectly Lorentz invariant, causal QED. A detailed discussion can also be found in Ref. 85.
The absorber theory is manifestly causal due to the lightcone integral in Eq. (23a). The absorbing boundary conditions are not required for causality, but they ensure approximate forward causation, see Ref. 56.
Overall, since all these formulations are just different ways of interpreting Maxwell's equations, it is clear that relativistic causality is preserved in any physical process described in these frameworks. Nevertheless, even while being causal, a non-local ontology is admitted by relativity. This peculiarity is at the core of other seeming puzzles of classical electromagnetism, such as the question how the Jefimenko equations84 for and can be causal despite the Coulomb equation, , suggesting the opposite.83,86 The Coulomb equation seems acausal because , and, thus, the longitudinal part of depends instantaneously on the charge density ρ. To see explicitly that this instantaneous dependence is consistent with causality, one can use the dynamical Maxwell equations to write . All relativistic field theories with first class constraints have the property that instantaneous constraint equations are compatible with the causal evolution.
As already discussed, the GIE proposal as well as its EM analog heavily relies on the notion of locality, which lies at the core of the LOCC argument. In Subsection III C, we have concluded that locality is not a prerequisite; instead, it is a matter of choice to formulate physics in a local or non-local way. This discussion addresses similar questions and shares some similarities with the correspondence between DeWitt and Aharonov and Bohm75,87 (see also Ref. 88) shortly after their seminal work on the “Significance of the EM potentials in quantum theory.”89 In particular, in Ref. 75, DeWitt asks: Which is more significant, the fact that non-local formulations of causal theories exist which deal only with observables, or the fact that in all known cases, local formulations in terms of potential also exist? Continues with the following statement: In a similar vein, the author disagrees with the assertion of Aharonov and Bohm that quantum electrodynamics is ultimately determined by the requirement that it is expressible in a local form. QED is really determined by experiment.
This assessment aligns with our interpretation of the electromagnetic analogue of the GIE proposal. QED is determined by experiment, and it cannot discern a local from a non-local formulation. The underlying ontology corresponds to a metaphysical statement which by no means is tested. Thus, any formulation of QED, local or non-local, is equally viable, as long as the experimental outcomes are indistinguishable. For the EM analogue of GIE, this implies that one cannot unambiguously infer the existence of local mediators.
IV. THE GRAVITATIONAL CASE: QUANTIZED MEDIATORS OR NON-LOCAL ALTERNATIVES?
Above we discussed the electromagnetic version of the GIE experiment. We showed that conclusions beyond the non-relativistic limit are ambiguous because there is always an alternative explanation possible that generates entanglement non-locally, and, thus, the LOCC argument does not unambiguously imply quantization of mediators. It is conceivable that similar dual arguments based on either a local mediator theory or a non-local theory could apply to quantum gravity. This is, indeed, the case for weak gravity.
A. Local mediators: Weak-field quantum gravity in Lorentz gauge
B. No mediators: Weak-field quantum gravity in Poisson gauge
The Hamiltonian in Poisson gauge (29) can generate entanglement between two masses through the exchange of the physical spin-2 gravitons (the term ) and/or the non-local interaction between the quantized matter degrees of freedom (second and third line, which are both non-local). In the regime in which gravitational radiation is irrelevant, as it is the case for the GIE proposal, the entanglement is generated non-locally via direct matter interactions. In direct analogy to the toy model for QED entanglement generation, as discussed in Sec. III, one can now directly compute how the two masses entangle in this non-local formulation. The computation carries over one-to-one: the non-local term in (29) that involves generates the entanglement, since all other terms are negligible. No mediators appear at any stage of the calculation. In contrast, the authors of Ref. 74 arrive at this same interaction term above in the local Lorentz gauge, where quantized virtual mediators appear as discussed in Sec. IV A—the two physical predictions are, thus, equivalent, as expected, but the ontology can be local or non-local. Additionally, also in the Lorentz gauge, the authors show explicitly that no virtual spin-2 gravitons appear in the non-relativistic limit relevant for GIE, only the auxiliary, unobservable mediators. Thus, neither in the Lorentz gauge nor in the Poisson gauge do the spin-2 gravitons contribute (their contribution is gauge invariant), not even in virtual processes.
Overall, from the non-local picture presented here in the Poisson gauge, the relevant interaction term appears without the involvement of any local mediators. Thus, one cannot use the LOCC argument to infer the existence of quantized mediators in the gravitational case either.
In this context, we also refer to Zel'dovich and Novikov,94 who say: [a] popular but untrue assertion is that the gravitational interaction is due to an “exchange of gravitons.” [⋯] The difference in character between the longitudinal and the transverse fields clearly illustrates the absurdity of a literal interpretation of the phrase, “Interaction is an exchange of quanta.” While this quote highlights the caveats of a strictly local interpretation and emphasizes the equivalent non-local one, in our view, the two are simply equally viable. Any preference boils down to imposing additional assumptions about the nature of physics that are not distinguishable in relativity, such as imposing that only physical degrees of freedom are quantized, or alternatively that physics is strictly local. Only if the latter is imposed, such that the equivalent non-local description is simply excluded by hand, which can the LOCC argument be used to indirectly infer quantized mediators of gravity.
C. No mediators: Weak-field quantum gravity as absorber theory
Additionally, in analogy to electromagnetism, in the weak-field regime of gravity, there also exists an absorber formulation,95,96 which would comprise a weak-field quantum gravity after source mass quantization. Thus, the same ambiguity that we highlighted in the electromagnetic case also exists in the weak-field limit of General Relativity: Mediators can be fully removed from the theory by changing to a fundamentally non-local source and absorber ontology. Within this framework alone, it is, therefore, not possible to conclude that entanglement is generated through quantized, local mediators from the outcome of the GIE experiment and validity of post-Newtonian gravity alone.
However, no absorber formulation of full general relativity has been found so far. It is currently not known if a classical absorber theory for gravity can exist at all. Attempts to construct absorber theories of non-Abelian gauge theories and gravity are incomplete96–101 or failed.102 Note that the gravitational theory developed by Hoyle and Narlikar103 is not an absorber theory of gravity since the metric appears as degree of freedom in the action.104,105 There are gravitational absorber theories that correctly reproduce the post-Newtonian limit of GR for N particles, the Einstein–Infeld–Hoffman equations,106 see Refs. 96 and 107. This limit, however, does not include the effects of gravitational radiation. Thus, whether a loophole to the LOCC argument in the form of a non-local absorber theory applies also to gravitational interactions depends on whether one can construct a complete absorber theory for gravity, which is a fascinating open question.108
It is, nevertheless, conceivable that any hypothetical quantum theory of gravity that is theoretically acceptable and experimentally viable could share the ambiguity of QED of whether entanglement is produced through virtual longitudinal and scalar gravitons, or through a direct non-local interaction of quantized source masses. In the absence of such a theory of quantum gravity, the conceivable possibilities for interpreting gravitationally induced entanglement can only be broader. There are even arguments that suggest that any quantum gravity might exhibit fundamental non-locality.109–111 Thus, observing gravitationally induced entanglement does not tell us whether gravity is quantized unless we insist on assuming that quantum gravity is a local quantum field theory—and only the local ontology is permissible. The resilience of gravity to quantization and certain properties of gravity that suggest that it would have a locally finite dimensional Hilbert space, could be an indication that quantum gravity is at odds with being fundamentally a local quantum field theory. We, thus, have two possible sets of assumptions for general relativity: either being fundamentally a local quantum field theory or having some non-local interpretation. Neither our theoretical understanding today nor the GIE experiment can distinguish these two. Thus, also for gravity, the conclusion from the GIE experiment about quantized mediators depends on what prior assumptions we are willing to accept, but that are not imposed on us from our current understanding of physics.
V. PATH INTEGRALS
A. Electromagnetic case
To further clarify the differences in the various interpretations, here, we consider, in the electromagnetic case, the path integrals involved in the non-relativistic Coulomb case, Coulomb gauge QED, Lorenz gauge QED, and absorber theory. This formulation helps highlight the apparent paradoxes and their resolutions and fully clarifies the relation between all four cases in the electromagnetic case. Interestingly, the mathematical starting points of the various QED formulations are very different, but for the case of QED, they lead to identical physical outcomes.
Since the electromagnetic field is a gauge field with unphysical degrees of freedom, care needs to be taken when performing the path integral . There are several options. One can fix the gauge completely before performing the path integral, such as in Coulomb gauge, or one can include a gauge fixing term in the path integral. The latter can be effectively achieved by quantizing in Lorenz gauge following Gupta and Bleuler.68,69
The theory is called local if the Lagrangian density consists only of local polynomials of the current and fields (and its first and second derivatives). An example for a local Lagrangian is , whereas an example for a non-local Lagrangian density is with some kernel D. In any case, the action is given by .
1. QED in Lorenz gauge
2. QED in Coulomb gauge
3. QED absorber formulation
4. Non-relativistic Coulomb interactions
5. Equivalent predictions
Interestingly, the path integrals for QED in Lorenz gauge, QED in Coulomb gauge and the absorber theory, all lead to identical predictions for amplitudes after renormalization.65 It, thus, becomes obvious that the question of “what produces the entanglement in the electromagnetic GIE experiment?” is ambiguous, even in the relativistic descriptions. To answer the question in all these cases, we just need to look at what determines the dominant part of phase factors of the four different semi-classical paths of the two particles (see Fig. 1, where the four distances are LL, LR, RL, and RR). In Lorenz gauge QED, the phase is due to the auxiliary fields, also known as “virtual photons,” in Coulomb gauge QED and the Coulomb theory, it is due to auxiliary fields slaved to the particles due to the constraint equation, and in the absorber theory, it is due to direct particle interactions on the lightcone in the complete absence of any field. Coulomb gauge QED, non-relativistic Coulomb theory, and absorber theory, thus, share the property that entanglement is established without any mediators.
6. Causality
The path integral formulation again suggests that apart from the picture in the Lorentz gauge, entanglement in QED seems to be established in the same acausal manner as in Coulomb theory, even though QED is a fundamentally causal theory. This arises because in QED, the physical photons do not contribute to the entanglement in the proposed experiment in the limit of very slow wave-packet splitting and merging, and, thus, the entangling phase factor in the path integral is dominated by the Coulomb field that is sourced instantaneously from the charge distribution rather than the retarded charge distribution. Nevertheless, the QED results are fully causal in all formulations: the on-shell combined with leads to a manifestly causal expression, which coincides with the expression appearing in the absorber theory. Interestingly, this precise expression has been explicitly used in Ref. 51 (not in the context of absorber theories) to establish that no entanglement would be produced in a GIE type experiment if the splitting and merging of the wave packets happened at spacelike separations. We, thus, see that while dominates the phase factor in the GIE experiment, one needs to include to restore causality, or, generally, whenever a near field approximation is not a good approximation and retardation effects become important. At spacelike distances, the would-be entanglement of is exactly canceled by .
B. Gravitational path integrals
The discussion carries over analogously to linearized gravity. In the case of non-linear gravity, the equivalence between a field path integral and an absorber theory will likely break down. However, one could simply postulate a theory of quantum gravity in which the path integral only involves matter, and the gravitational field is “slaved” to the matter configuration like in an absorber theory. In other words, one would associate with each quantum state of matter a correspondingly sourced gravitational field and allow for coherent superpositions of such source-gravity entangled states. This type of “simplified” quantum gravity model can be a useful approach, as in, e.g., Refs. 112 and 113 and would correctly predict the GIE experiment because it automatically has the same linearized weak-field limit that was assumed to hold for a “proper” quantum gravity theory in which geometries are summed over in the path integral independently of the matter.51 The two situations would likely only be distinguishable in the strong field regime, where graviton loops contribute in the latter case but not in the former. As long as we limit ourselves to weak gravity, however, the equivalence between the local and non-local path integral formulations as discussed in the QED case remains.
VI. COSMOLOGY AND SIGNATURES OF QUANTUM GRAVITY
In the previous chapters, we have considered the GIE experiment from the point of view of different theoretical (or even meta-physical) assumptions. Here, we discuss how the same assumptions applied to cosmology can provide similar conclusions from already existing observations.
The prediction of the cosmic microwave background (CMB) temperature fluctuation correlation from inflation, thus, required the quantization of the weak-field gravitational field many decades before the GIE proposal. Several generic a priori predictions based on canonical single field inflation made 40 years ago114,115 have been confirmed observationally, such that one might say that evidence for quantizing weak-field gravity already exists today. Indeed, mean-field theory as mentioned in Sec. II would not be adequate to predict the temperature fluctuations of the Cosmic Microwave Background within the inflationary paradigm, as no fluctuations would be produced at all during inflation.
In principle, the inflationary paradigm also predicts the amplification and stretching of gravitational radiation, which leaves a distinctive imprint in the polarization of the temperature fluctuations, the so-called primordial B-mode polarization. Currently, there are only upper bounds on the amplitude of this type of anisotropy, which has already ruled out certain simple shapes of the inflation potential.120 Observation of primordial B-modes would be evidence for the quantum nature of the spin-2 graviton. However, as discussed above, within the assumptions of the GIE proposal, already the CMB fluctuations as observed indicate the quantization of the Newtonian part in similar spirit to the GIE proposal.
Finally, we note that fields evolving under their self-gravity or on an expanding space can exhibit more intricate quantum features. For instance, the quantum states of the inflation or of a light scalar field comprising the dark matter as well as the quantum state of gravitational radiation can get squeezed.121–124 Cosmological observations might, thus, provide unique tests of weak-field quantum gravity,125–127 or even of genuine superpositions in more speculative scenarios,128 which should these scalars fields exist.
VII. DISCUSSION
A. Newtonian quantization in GIE and cosmology
What then does the GIE experiment teach us in addition to current cosmological observations, as discussed above? First of all, not everyone might believe in the inflationary paradigm: the conclusion that gravity is quantized requires a prior belief in the current standard inflation paradigm where it is sourced by quantum fields. Furthermore, while cosmological observations of the cosmic microwave background are very accurate, the object that is used to study the quantization of gravity has been created more than 13 billion years ago and modulated by unknown components such as dark matter and dark energy. Any independent and more direct evidence for the quantization of weak-field gravity is, thus, still very valuable. Furthermore, the GIE experiment probes more directly the fact that the gravitational field can be put into superposition, which is necessary for entanglement between source masses to arise. In contrast, in the cosmological setting, it is quantum fluctuations of masses that source fluctuations in the gravitational field. While this is a direct consequence of quantizing the gravitational field, it is conceivable that this effect can be mimicked by an entirely classical theory, e.g., the standard classical weak-field Einstein equations augmented by a stochastic yet classical noise term that sources fluctuations maybe during a (classical) inflation. In other words, it is conceivable that the gravitational field is never put into superposition or any quantum state, albeit considered implausible in the cosmology community. The strength of the GIE experiment lies in the difficulty of alternative explanations for producing gravitationally induced entanglement that would not require the gravitational field to exist in superposition during the experiment—there are, however, some suggestions for alternative models46,129 in which LOCC does not necessarily hold since quantum physics is modified. Overall, observing gravitationally induced entanglement would give more direct support to the idea that the gravitational field can exist in superposition.
B. Ambiguous and unambiguous conclusions from the GIE experiment
As we have shown, the conclusions from GIE vary depending on what set of assumptions one uses as a starting point. At the core, the experiment probes what has been discussed in Sec. II: The expected result is based on non-relativistic quantum mechanics with gravitational interactions, which is quantized source masses interacting through a Newtonian potential . Gravity is introduced into the non-relativistic quantum theory the same way as the electric Coulomb potential. The experiment, if successful, thus, unambiguously confirms that gravity is sourced coherently by a mass in superposition, from which one can conclude that Newtonian gravity is coherently associated with a spatial superposition of the source. To date, such a superposition of Newtonian potential remains unverified and untested, and, thus, GIE would provide a test of physics in a new regime. The experiment can also rule out alternative models, such as a mean-field source for the gravitational potential or a classical channel model.16 Of course, any unexpected result would hint at new physics.
Going beyond these conclusions, however, is ambiguous. The original aim of the GIE proposals was to draw conclusions about the nature of quantum gravity by assuming that this is a relativistic and local theory of which the non-relativistic limit with its inherent non-locality is merely an artifact. However, as we have shown, even if one accepts this reasonable starting point, still no unambiguous conclusion about the underlying mediators can be made. This is because non-local entanglement generation is perfectly allowed even within relativistic physics. QED is a good example that locality is not a necessary assumption and does not need to be imposed on such a relativistic parent theory—as opposed to causality. This is not simply an issue of gauge, but that locality is not necessarily satisfied for the underlying ontology even in relativity. This is important here, as the proposed tests are of indirect nature, and the underlying ontology is central for the interpretation of the outcomes. If a non-local explanation is possible, then LOCC is simply not able to distinguish between a quantum and a classical mediator. Thus, while the absorber formulation may be considered as a “quirk” of the theory, it still shows that locality need not be satisfied at the fundamental level, even if all observations are causal. For gravity, it remains an open question if an absorber theory can capture all of general relativity, but it exists for the weak-field limit. Moreover, it is conceivable that quantum gravity is fundamentally non-local in some way. In all these cases, the LOCC argument breaks down, since the locality condition is no longer satisfied, and, thus, the observation of entanglement generation does not necessarily imply quantized gravitational mediators.
Thus, it is only when locality is imposed as an additional condition that one can conclude quantization of mediators in such indirect tests. While we agree that the additional assumption of locality is not just allowed but also plausible and intuitive,130,131 we have no indication that it must be satisfied in nature at the fundamental level. A serious drawback is that imposing locality introduces additional, fictitious degrees of freedom, such as scalar and longitudinal photons in QED, and analogous types of new gravitons in weak-field quantum gravity, which can never be directly observed. Yet, they are responsible for mediating entanglement in this picture. The other picture, which is non-local, gets rid of these unphysical degrees of freedom and, thus, has its own merits. Fundamentally, causality seems to be the underlying principle in all these formulations, and locality only a convenient consequence in one of them. Thus, the only unambiguous statement one can draw from the GIE experiments with regard to mediators is that if one pre-assumes an underlying local field theory, then such a field theory would need to include quantized mediators. However, this assumption is very restrictive in that it artificially excludes perfectly valid non-local formulations. Our cosmology example shows that if the same assumptions about the nature of gravity are accepted, in addition to the standard inflationary scenario, then already the observed CMB fluctuations are sufficient to deduce quantum fluctuations of the gravitational field.
C. Agents and locality
From a quantum information perspective, the GIE proposal involves two localized agents (Alice and Bob) situated close to their respective particle. Each agent directly manipulates only their respective nearby particle locally (through the particle's spin in the GIE proposal26) so as to create the spatial superposition and subsequently interfere the particle's wave function to infer the creation of entanglement. If, however, the two particles interact non-locally, then Alice's local interaction with her particle will inadvertently and unavoidably also affect Bob's particle non-locally, and vice versa. Thus, the GIE proposal's experimental setup does not guarantee that the two agents perform only local operations because the gravitational interaction between the particles is not necessarily local. The LOCC theorem in combination with witnessing entanglement does, therefore, not imply the existence of quantized mediators since a necessary condition for the theorem to apply—locality—is not necessarily present and cannot be tested for.
As we discussed in Sec. III C, in the specific non-local theories studied in this paper in which quantum physics is unmodified, entanglement is necessarily and by construction produced quantum mechanically. Our point is that the existence of the quantum nature of the underlying system that generates entanglement could not have been inferred by merely invoking the LOCC argument alone. Even if entanglement is observed, it may be produced by some process that may correspond to some underlying system that is not quantum mechanical in the usual sense.132,133 We note here that it is, therefore, also interesting to exactly quantify the expected entanglement and probe for possible deviations.
D. Superpositions of geometries
Can one draw conclusions about the quantum nature of gravity beyond mediators? It was pointed out in several previous works50,51 that it is not the quantum nature of mediators the GIE proposal is sensitive to, but the ability of the gravitational field to exist in a quantum superposition. Can one gain insights on quantum gravity from that alone?
A compelling interpretation is that the successful experiment shows that geometries of space-times exist in superposition. This is based on additional assumptions that we have not yet discussed: The extrapolation of classical general relativity (GR) and its ontology into the quantum domain. In this view, the Newtonian limit is just a limiting case of what is space-time geometry, and any superpositions of the Newtonian field correspond to superpositions of geometries in the context of GR. One way to see this is in the path integral formulation of the gravitational case: The phase difference between the semi-classical paths of the particles is dominated by solutions of the classical Einstein equations sourced by the semi-classical matter configurations entering the superposition.51 In this sense, the GIE experiment would show that geometry can be put in superposition. This is true, no matter which gauge one adopts, or if one thinks of the geometry as fundamental or arising from virtual gravitons, the constraint equation, or direct particle interaction on the light cone. In all cases, the superposition of effective geometry is the origin of the entanglement. The only way to avoid this conclusion is to find a viable gravitational theory that is not geometrical in the quantum regime and/or to replace the path integral, and thus quantum mechanics, by some other theory in this limit. While we are not aware of any theory of gravity consistent with observations that is not geometrical, it is conceivable that the path integral formula is not correct if contributions of different geometries would lead to an observable effect. For instance in Penrose's gravitational collapse mechanism, if the wave packets in the GIE experiment were kept a sufficiently long time apart before they are attempted to be merged, only one of the four semi-classical contributions to the path integral (LL, LR, RL, and RR) would survive according to Penrose (the other branches are “dying” before the matter wave packets are attempted to be merged, and, thus, no merging actually happens), in which case we might expect the complete absence of entanglement and any other interference effect of the particles. In general, a modification of the path integral that would lead to the expected entanglement without having geometries in superposition would have to be drastically different from standard quantum mechanics. For instance, we could imagine that each path was weighted with a phase produced by the gravitational mean field (thus geometry is not in a superposition), but there is an additional contribution to the phases of the four semi-classical paths (LL, LR, RL, and RR) that involve non-local interactions between particles that have no geometric interpretation. While this is highly contrived, we mention this possibility only to highlight that GIE does not provide any direct evidence of geometries in superposition beyond the Newtonian limit, and possible deviations beyond this limit are at least conceivable, such as in Refs. 46 and 129. Indeed, some recent works highlight the possible difference between superposed geometries that have drastically different curvatures and those that differ only by a displaced source mass, as in the GIE case.134,135
Overall, the various conclusions and possibilities for new physics are summarized in Fig. 2.
E. Comparison to other works on interpretations of GIE
Various recent works have considered the implications and interpretations of the GIE experiment. Here, we briefly compare them to our results.
While not directly addressing the GIE proposal, an interesting recent related line of research has emerged that focuses on Gedankenexperiments and what they imply for the quantization of gravity.23,24,52,136,137 Belenchia et al.24 show how a seeming paradox arises for the interferometric which-way information between two space-like separated masses, but it can be avoided when quantizing gravitational radiation. Such arguments relate to GIE, as they operate in the same Newtonian limit and support the view of the need to quantize gravity. Nevertheless, the paradox in such Gedankenexperiments can also be resolved without quantized radiation, and, thus, the question of quantization from these arguments remains inconclusive.25,138
Shortly after the GIE proposals, Anastopoulos and Hu pointed out in Ref. 45 that due to the static Newtonian limit in GIE, the physical mediators do not play a role, and that the mediator-interpretation is misguided. The authors argued that no quantization of the mediators can, therefore, be inferred from the Newtonian limit and discussed it further in Refs. 139 and 140. This aligns with what we discuss in the present manuscript as well, mainly in Sec. III where we show that (unphysical) mediators only appear when a specific gauge choice is made. We make the additional observation that both local and non-local formulations are not gauge artifacts, but viable interpretations of known relativistic physics.
In a recent work, Bose et al.74 show how gravitational entanglement is explicitly generated in a local picture, in analogy with a previous work by Franson,71 as we also use in Sec. III A. The toy model involves virtual mediators, albeit not the physical ones. However, this demonstration alone is insufficient to infer their existence, and it merely shows that it is possible to describe entanglement in this form. One can equivalently describe the creation non-locally, as we show in Sec. III B and Subsection 1 of the Appendix. This invalidates somewhat the claims in Ref. 74, where it is argued that the presence of virtual gravitons is essential for the masses to get entangled. The same can be achieved non-locally without gravitons in this proposal, as we showed in Sec. IV and Subsection 2 of the Appendix.
Providing a complementary perspective on GIE and inferred quantization, Carney has proven the existence of quantized physical gravitons based on three assumptions:49 that quantized source particles interact via a potential in the non-relativistic limit, that the S matrix theory is unitary, and that it is Lorentz invariant. This seems in contradiction with the discussion in our work here, which highlights that a quantized absorber theory of weak-field gravity provides an alternative theory without gravitons. The resolution of this seeming contradiction is a loophole in Carney's proof. If one is willing to make the cosmological assumption that the far future contains a complete gravitational absorber, then the potential, the unitarity, and the Lorentz invariance do not require the existence of physical graviton states, or a Hilbert space associated with such states. This is discussed in more detail in Subsection 3 of the Appendix.
It was pointed out by Rovelli and Christodoulou that the fundamental mediators of gravity are not the central objects of interest in the GIE setup. The authors instead highlight the quantum nature of the sources and conclude that an expected outcome in the GIE experiment would imply that gravitational fields can exist in superposition.50 Superposition of geometries, as discussed in Sec. VII D, is then inferred from an extension of the Newtonian superpositions to general relativistic superpositions.
In a recent paper, Christodoulou et al.51 analyze GIE starting from a relativistic description based on path integrals, in order to highlight the inherent locality of entanglement generation in the relativistic setting. However, as we have discussed in Secs. III and V, relativistic Lorentz invariance does not necessarily mean that physics has to be local, but that causality has to be preserved. The local interpretation is only true for the formulation in the Lorentz gauge, which is what is exclusively used in Ref. 51. The same can be described in terms of non-local processes in the path integral formulation, both in a Poisson gauge and in terms of absorber theory, as we shown in Sec. V. While a modified setup that allows for retardation effects as proposed in Ref. 51 would involve local terms also in the Poisson gauge, the absorber non-local loophole still remains.
Finally, we mention that some alternative models have been proposed that do not involve the expected quantized Newtonian fields but that can still explain a positive outcome of the GIE experiment.46,47,129 These unorthodox semi-classical models are interesting test theories that warrant further study, at the very least as possible test theories against which the expected predictions can be probed and to design schemes that may distinguish them.
VIII. CONCLUSIONS
In this paper, we have critically assessed possible conclusions that one can draw from observing gravitationally induced entanglement. We have shown that entanglement can be generated by quantized mediators, but that such an interpretation is not unique. The possibility of non-local generation of entanglement is also viable even within known relativistic physics (absorber theory being one example), and, thus, no conclusion can be drawn about mediators unless the locality condition is additionally imposed. While locality is a choice and not fundamental in both QED and general relativity, causality is always preserved even in non-local formulations. The experiment, nevertheless, probes quantum aspects of gravity independently of the LOCC argument, as it involves superpositions of gravitational source masses, demonstrating the creation of superpositions of the Newtonian gravitational field.
Any interpretation beyond this relies on assumptions about the nature of quantum gravity which may or may not be true, and, thus, remains ambiguous. If locality is elevated to a fundamental assumption, then LOCC, indeed, predicts the existence of quantized mediators if GIE is witnessed. Intense debates about the proposal, thus, reach different conclusions, depending on what prior assumptions one is willing to accept as “most natural.” Since the proposed tests are of indirect nature, the choice for the underlying ontology is crucial for the conclusions one can draw. The electromagnetic case differs somewhat from the gravitational one, as the former can always be cast in a non-local absorber formulation, while gravity is only known in the Newtonian and post-Newtonian limits to have a non-local absorber picture. In both cases, also an interpretation with local mediators of entanglement is permitted, although the involved mediators are not the observable physical bosons. However, since non-local formulations are permitted as well, observing the expected entanglement would be compatible with both the non-existence and existence of local quantized mediators. We also showed that under reasonable prior assumptions, one can already claim tests of the quantum nature of the Newtonian gravitational field in cosmological observations. Such a claim, however, relies additionally on the validity of the usual inflationary paradigm.
In sum, there are three types of conclusions one can draw from GIE: (i) The experiment can probe some alternative theories that would yield an unexpected outcome, such as Penrose collapse, classical local channel models, or mean field theory. (ii) An expected result will show that spatial superpositions of matter coherently source Newtonian gravity, yielding superpositions of Newtonian fields. The caveat is that if one assumes the usual inflationary paradigm, matter in quantum states sourcing Newtonian gravity is already shown in current CMB observations. (iii) If one assumes an underlying relativistic theory for gravity, different interpretations exist on how entanglement is generated. One of them includes local mediators, which, however, are not the usual observable bosons. In such an interpretation, these mediators have to be quantized. However, entanglement generation can equally be described in terms of non-local processes in the relativistic setting, and, thus, induced entanglement is insufficient to conclude the quantization of mediators. Overall, our results clarify that while quantum superpositions of gravitational sources are probed in such proposals, claims about mediators remain ambiguous, both in the electromagnetic and in the gravitational setups.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
The authors acknowledge Erik Aurell, Fawad Hassan, Myungshik Kim, Jonas Larson, Florian Niedermann, Germaine Tobar, Frank Wilczek, and Ting Yu for useful discussions and feedback. This work was supported by the Swedish Research Council under Grant No. 2019–05615, the European Research Council under Grant No. 742104, and The Branco Weiss Fellowship—Society in Science.
AUTHOR DECLARATIONS
Conflict of Interest
The authors have no conflicts to disclose.
Author Contributions
Vasileios Fragkos and Michael Kopp contributed equally to this work.
Vasileios Fragkos: Conceptualization (equal); Writing – original draft (equal). Michael Kopp: Conceptualization (equal); Writing – original draft (equal); Writing – review & editing (equal). Igor Pikovski: Conceptualization (equal); Writing – review & editing (equal).
DATA AVAILABILITY
Data sharing is not applicable to this article as no new data were created or analyzed in this study.
APPENDIX: Supplementary calculations related to the non-local formulations
1. QED in Coulomb gauge
It is crucial to notice that despite the various non-local (instantaneous) pieces that appear in the formulation, QED in Coulomb gauge describes causal physical processes.81–84,86
2. Weak-field gravity in Poisson gauge
We note in passing that, in analogy with electrodynamics, where the Poisson (constraint) equation enforces charge conservation , in the weak-field of GR, gauge invariance, namely, invariance under infinitesimal change of the coordinates , implies four conserved quantities . This equation shows the limitations of weak-field gravity since it contradicts the equations of motion of matter. This inconsistency can only be avoided after resuming all perturbation orders to get back full general relativity.
The set of equations (A15)–(A19) describe the causal dynamics of the metric components in Poisson gauge. Neglecting some pieces, or focusing only on the constraint equations, would erroneously lead to the conclusion that GR in the weak-field limit describes non-causal physics.
3. Graviton existence theorem and the absorber loophole
It was recently proven in Ref. 49 that unitarity and Lorentz invariance, together with the assumption that non-relativistically gravity is a potential, imply the existence of physical gravitons, or in other words, the existence of quantum states of gravitational degrees of freedom. As we discussed in the main text, assuming locality and the LOCC argument does not directly allow one to conclude the existence of physical graviton states, only the existence of auxiliary or “unphysical” gravitons that can only appear in virtual processes. These gravitons are the analog of the scalar and longitudinal photons of QED.
It, therefore, seems that Carney's existence proof of physical gravitons not only is stronger than the LOCC argument but also already shows the existence of the graviton without the need to perform the GIE experiment. More strikingly, Carney's proof, which is also formulated in the weak-field regime of gravity, seems to be in contradiction with the fact that an absorber theory of weak-field quantum gravity is unitary, Lorentz invariant, and has a classical potential. Thus, the properties that Carney assumed are present in an absorber theory, but that by construction has no gravitons!
In this appendix, we point out the hidden additional assumption that goes into the proof and allows one to infer the existence of the graviton, and that dropping this extra assumption is then consistent with the existence of a gravitational absorber theory that has no gravitons. To summarize our result: unitarity and Lorentz invariance, and the potential only imply the graviton if absorbing boundary conditions are excluded. This exclusion was the additional hidden assumption in Ref. 49.
Carney considered a tree-level process in which two masses are controlled electromagnetically, for instance, to produce the superpositions in the GIE experiment, and then interact through the potential. Considering a six-point amplitude, see upper left diagram in Fig. 3, involving the photon (curvy lines), massive particles (full lines), and gravitational interaction (dashed line), the existence of diagrams with on-shell graviton lines is derived, see the upper right diagram. The pole at has an imaginary residue. This residue is equal to the product of a pair of amplitudes, one shown in the upper right of Fig. 3, where the physical graviton (dashed line) is emitted into the final state. The disconnected line represents a trivial propagator. If this diagram, and, thus, physical graviton states did not exist, unitarity is violated. This was in a nutshell Carney's argument.
Now we come to the absorber loophole. In an absorber ontology, the diagram in the upper left of Fig. 3 is incomplete and misses the existence of absorber particles. While most absorber particles are not involved in any given scattering event, some always will be. This is indicated by the lower left diagram in Fig. 3. This “spectator” absorber allows then to restore unitarity through the diagram shown in the lower right. It absorbs the would-be graviton. In the absorber ontology, there are no on-shell gravitons, so the graviton pole does not exist in the absorber theory, and, thus, restoration of unitarity only requires proper consideration of absorbing boundary condition, and no introduction of graviton quantum states.
Note that absorbing boundary conditions do not exclude the existence of a physical graviton state, but they do not require such a state either. Thus, gravitons cannot be inferred from Carney's argument if absorbing boundary conditions are imposed.