The study of quantum correlation sets initiated by Tsirelson in the 1980s and originally motivated by questions in the foundations of quantum mechanics has more recently been tied to questions in quantum cryptography, complexity theory, operator space theory, group theory, and more. Synchronous correlation sets introduced by Paulsen et al. [J. Funct. Anal. 270, 2188–2222 (2016)] are a subclass of correlations that has proven particularly useful to study and arises naturally in applications. We show that any correlation that is almost synchronous, in a natural 1 sense, arises from a state and measurement operators that are well-approximated by a convex combination of projective measurements on a maximally entangled state. This extends a result of Paulsen et al. [J. Funct. Anal. 270, 2188–2222 (2016)] that applies to exactly synchronous correlations. Crucially, the quality of approximation is independent of the dimension of the Hilbert spaces or of the size of the correlation. Our result allows one to reduce the analysis of many classes of nonlocal games, including rigidity properties, to the case of strategies using maximally entangled states that are generally easier to manipulate.

For finite sets X,Y,A and B, a quantum correlation is an element of the set

Cq(X,Y,A,B)=ψAaxBbyψxyab:ψHAHB,xX,yY,AaxaA POVM on HA,BbybB POVM on HB,

where HA and HB range over all finite-dimensional Hilbert spaces and a POVM (positive operator-valued measure) on a Hilbert space H is a collection of positive semidefinite operators on H that sum to identity. For each X,Y,A,B, the set Cq(X,Y,A,B) is convex, as can be seen by taking direct sums, but there are X,Y,A,B such that it is not closed.1 We write Cq for the union of Cq(X,Y,A,B) over all finite X,Y,A and B.

A strategy is a tuple S=(ψ,A,B) such that ψHAHB is a state (i.e., a unit vector), A=Aax is a collection of POVM on HA, and B=Bby is a collection of POVM on HB. (The finite-dimensional Hilbert spaces HA and HB as well as the index sets X,Y,A, and B are generally left implicit in the notation.) Given a strategy S, we say that Sinduces the correlation (Cx,y,a,b=ψAaxBbyψ)xyab.

The study of the set of quantum correlations Cq and its relation to the set of classical correlations C, defined as the convex hull of those correlations that can be induced using a state ψ that is a tensor product ψ=ψAψBHAHB, is of importance in the foundations of quantum mechanics. The fact that CCq, as first shown by Bell2 and often termed “quantum nonlocality,” underlies the field of device-independent quantum cryptography and gives rise to the study of entanglement witnesses, protocols for delegated quantum computation, and questions in quantum complexity theory; we refer to Ref. 3 for references. Following the foundational work of Tsirelson,4 multiple variants of the set of quantum correlations have been introduced and their study is connected to a range of problems in mathematics, including operator space theory,5,6 group theory,7 and combinatorics.8 

In this paper, we consider a subset of Cq introduced in Ref. 9 and called the synchronous setCqs. It is defined as the union of all Cqs(X,A), where Cqs(X,A) is the subset of Cq(X,X,A,A) that contains all those correlations C that satisfy Cx,x,a,b = 0 whenever ab. This set arises naturally in the study of certain classes of nonlocal games. In general, a nonlocal game G is specified by a distribution ν on X×Y and a function D:X×Y×A×B0,1. A nonlocal game gives rise to a linear function on Cq(X,Y,A,B) through the quantity

ωq(G;C)=x,yν(x,y)a,bD(x,y,a,b)Cx,y,a,b.

Given a game G, one is interested in its quantum valueωq(G), which is defined as the supremum over all CCq of ωq(G;C). A game G such that X=Y, A=B, ν(x, x) > 0 for all x, and D(a, b|x, x) = 0 for all x and ab is called a synchronous game. Any such game has the property that ωq(G;C)=1 can only be obtained by a CCqs. Synchronous games arise naturally in applications; see, e.g., the classes of graph homomorphism games10 or linear system games.11 (Linear system games are projection games, which can be turned into synchronous games by taking their “square;” see Ref. 12.) The set Cqs retains most of the interesting geometric aspects of Cq, and in particular, it is convex and non-closed.12 

A key property of synchronous correlations that makes them more amenable to study is the following fact shown in Ref. 9. For every synchronous correlation C, there is a family of strategies Sλ=(ψλ,Aλ,Bλ)λΛ and a measure μ on Λ such that for each λ, ψλ=ψme(dλ) with

ψme(dλ)=1dλi=1dλuiuiHλHλ,
(1)

where dλ=dim(Hλ) and ui:1idλ is an orthonormal family in Hλ, and each measurement Aaλ,x and Bbλ,y consists entirely of projections, and moreover, for all x, y, a, b, we have

Cx,y,a,b=λψλAaλ,xBbλ,yψλdμ(λ).
(2)

When ψme(dλ) takes the form in (1), we can express

ψλAaλ,xBbλ,yψλ=1dλTrAaλ,xBbλ,yT,
(3)

where Tr(·) is the usual matrix trace and XT denotes the transpose with respect to the basis ui. The fact that synchronous correlations are “tracial” in the sense given by (2) and (3) contributes largely to their appeal. In contrast, there are correlations CCq such that C cannot be induced, even approximately, using a convex combination of strategies using states of the form (1) in any dimension; see Ref. 13 for an example. Such correlations tend to be more difficult to study and their main interest lies in their existence, e.g., they can provide entanglement witnesses for states that are not maximally entangled.

We consider strategies S=(ψ,A,B) that are almost synchronous, where the default to synchronicity is measured by the quantity

δsync(C;ν)=ExνabCx,x,a,b,
(4)

where ν is some distribution on X. This averaged 1 distance is motivated by applications to nonlocal games, which we describe below. Informally, our main result is that any strategy S that induces a correlation C is well-approximated by a convex combination of strategies Sλ each using a maximally entangled state, where the approximation is controlled by δsync(Cν) for any ν (ν also enters in the measure of approximation between S and the Sλ) and, crucially for applications, does not depend on the dimension of ψ or the size of the sets X and A. In particular, each Sλ gives rise to a synchronous correlation Cλ such that λCλC in a suitable 1 sense. Moreover, and crucially for the applications that we describe next, specific structural properties of the Sλ, such as algebraic relations between some of the measurement operators, can be transferred to the strategy S. A simplified version of our theorem specialized to the case of a single measurement can be stated as follows:

Theorem.
There are universal constantsc, C > 0 such that the following holds. LetHbe a finite-dimensional Hilbert space andψHHa state. Then, there is a finite set Λ, a distributionμon Λ, and, for eachλ ∈ Λ, a stateψλthat is maximally entangled on a subspaceHλHλHHsuch that lettingρbe the reduced density ofψon the first factor andρλ be the reduced density ofψλonHλH,
ρ=Eλμρλ.
(5)
Moreover, letAbe a finite set andAaaAbe an arbitrary measurement onH. Then, there is a projective measurementAaλonHλsuch that
EλμaAaAaλIdψλ2C1aψAaAaψc.
(6)

For the complete statement and additional remarks, see Theorem 3.1. The first part of the theorem (5) is very simple to obtain; it is the second part that is meaningful. In particular, since ψλ is a maximally entangled state, the approximation on the left-hand side can be seen as a form of weighted approximation over certain (overlapping) diagonal blocks of A. The fact that the spaces Hλ and the states ψλ depend on ψ only allows us to apply the theorem repeatedly for different measurements in order to decompose an arbitrary strategy as a convex combination of projective maximally entangled strategies, with the right-hand side in (6) replaced by sync(C;ν)c for a ν of one’s choice (which naturally will also appear on the left-hand side).

A consequence of the theorem is that any CCq̄ that is also synchronous can be approximated by elements of Cqs; this is because any sequence of approximations to C taken from Cq must, by definition, be almost synchronous and so Theorem 3.1 can be applied. (For this observation, it is crucial that the approximation provided in Theorem 3.1 does not depend on the dimension of the Hilbert spaces; however, it could depend on the size of C.) This particular application was already shown in Ref. 12 (Theorem 3.6).

Our result and its formulation are motivated by the study of nonlocal games. For a strategy S, we write ωq(G;S) for ωq(G;C), where C is the correlation induced by S. Recall that the game value ωq(G) is the supremum over all strategies of ωq(G;S). The fact that the supremum is taken over Cq and not Cqs is motivated by applications to entanglement tests, cryptography, and complexity theory, as in those contexts, there is no a priori reason to enforce hard constraints of the form Cx,x,a,b = 0; indeed, such a constraint cannot be verified with absolute confidence in any statistical test.

Given a game and a strategy S, it is possible to obtain statistical confidence that ωq(G;S)ωq(G)ε for finite ɛ > 0 by playing the game many times. For this reason, the characterization of nearly optimal strategies plays a central role in applications of nonlocality. Recall that a synchronous game has the property that D(x, x, a, b) = 0 whenever ab. Given a synchronous game G such that furthermore ωq(G)=1, it follows that any strategy S for G such that ωq(G;S)ωq(G)ε must satisfy δsync(S;νdiag)=O(ε), where νdiag(x) = ν(x, x)/(∑xν(x′, x′)) and the constant implicit in the O(·) notation will, in general, depend on the weight that ν places on the diagonal. (In particular, a better bound on δsync will be obtained in cases when the distribution ν is not a uniform distribution, as the uniform distribution places weight 1|X| on the diagonal, which can be quite small.) Thus, nearly optimal strategies in synchronous games give rise to almost synchronous correlations. This conclusion may also hold for games that are not necessarily synchronous, for example, because the sets X and Y are disjoint; an example is the class of projection games that we consider in Sec. IV B. Examples of projection games include linear system games11 and games such as the low-degree test14 that play an important role in complexity theory.

Given the importance of studying nearly optimal strategies, the fact that for many games any nearly optimal strategy is almost synchronous ought to be useful. Our work allows one to reduce the analysis of almost synchronous strategies to that of exactly synchronous strategies in a broad variety of settings. The most direct application of our results is to the study of the phenomenon of rigidity, which seeks to extract necessary conditions of any strategy that is nearly optimal for a certain game. Informally, our results imply that a general rigidity result for a synchronous game can be obtained in an automatic manner from a rigidity result that applies only to perfectly synchronous strategies. In order for the implication to not lose factors depending on the size of the game in the approximation quality for the rigidity statement, it is sufficient that a high success probability in the game implies a low δsync(S;ν) for ν being the marginal distribution on either player’s questions in the game; see Corollary 4.1 and the remarks following it for further discussion. To give just one example, the entire analysis carried out in the recent work15 could be simplified by making all calculations with the maximally entangled state only, making manipulations of the “state-dependent distance” far easier to carry out. We refer to Sec. IV A for a precise formulation of how our main result can be used in this context as well as another application showing algebraic relations between measurement operators.

Given an almost synchronous strategy S=(ψ,A,B), it is not hard to show that the state and operators that underlie the strategy behave in an “approximately” cyclic manner, e.g., letting ρA denote the reduced density of ψ on HA, it holds that AaxρAρAAax10 for all x, a, where ‖·‖1 denotes the Schatten-1 norm; see, e.g., Ref. 16 (Lemma 3.7) for a precise statement. The strength of our result lies in showing that such relations imply an approximate decomposition in terms of maximally entangled strategies, where crucially the approximation quality does not depend on the dimension of the Hilbert space nor on the size of the sets X,Y,A or B. A similar decomposition implicitly appears in Ref. 7, where it is used to reduce the analysis of nearly optimal strategies for a specific linear system game to the case of maximally entangled strategies; in the context of that paper, the reduction is motivated by a connection with the study of approximate representations of a certain finitely presented group. The main technical ingredient that enables the reduction in Ref. 7 is also the main ingredient in the present paper, which can be seen as a direct generalization of the work done there. Informally, the key idea is to write any density matrix ρ as a convex combination of projections χλ(ρ), where λ is any non-negative real and χλ is the indicator of the interval [λ,+); see Lemma 2.11. The main additional observation needed is a calculation that originally appears in Ref. 17 and is restated as Lemma 2.12; informally, the calculation allows us to transfer approximate commutation conditions such as those obtained in Ref. 16 (Lemma 3.7) for any almost synchronous strategy to the same conditions, evaluated on the matrix χλ(ρ). The latter is a scaled multiple of the identity and is thus directly related to a maximally entangled state.

We use X,Y,A,B to denote finite sets. We use H to denote a finite-dimensional Hilbert space, which we generally endow with a canonical orthonormal basis i|i1,,d with d=dim(H). We use ‖·‖ to denote the operator norm (largest singular value) on H. Tr(·) is the trace on H and ‖·‖F is the Frobenius norm XF=Tr(XX)1/2 for any operator X on H, where X is the conjugate-transpose. A positive operator-valued measure (POVM), or measurement for short, on H is a finite collection of positive semidefinite operators AaaA such that ∑aAa = Id. A measurement Aa is projective if each Aa is a projection.

We use poly(δ) to denote any real-valued function f such that there exists constants C, c > 0 with |f(δ)| ≤ c for all non-negative real δ. The precise function f as well as the constants c, C may differ each time the notation is used. For a distribution ν on a finite set X, we write Exν for the expectation with respect to x with distribution ν.

Definition 2.1
(strategies and correlations). A strategyS is a tuple (ψ,A,B), where ψHAHB is a quantum state and A=Aaxrespectively,B=Bby is a collection of measurements on H indexed by xX and with outcomes aA (respectively, yY and bB). Any strategy induces a correlation, which is the collection of real numbers,
Cxyab=ψAaxBbyψ,(x,y)X×Y,(a,b)A×B.
The set of all correlations that arise from strategies of this form is denoted as
Cq(X,Y,A,B)R|XYAB|.

Definition 2.2

(synchronous correlations). For finite sets X and A, a correlation C=(Cx,y,a,b)Cq(X,X,A,A) is called synchronous if Cx,x,a,b = 0 for all xX and a,bA such that ab. Given a distribution ν on X, recall the definition of δsync(Cν) in (4). Given a strategy S, we also write δsync(S;ν) for δsync(Cν), where C is the correlation induced by S.

Definition 2.3
(PME strategies). A strategy S=(ψ,A,B) is symmetric if X=Y, A=B, ψHH takes the form
ψ=iλiuiuiHH,
(7)
where λi are non-negative and ui orthonormal, and for every x, a, Aax=(Bax)T with the transpose being taken with respect to the ui. Note that this implies that HA=HB and that ψ has the same reduced density on either subsystem. For a symmetric strategy, we write it as S=(ψ,A). A strategy is projective if all Aax and Bby are projections. It is maximally entangled if ψ is a maximally entangled state (1) on HAHB. We use the acronym “PME” to denote “symmetric projective maximally entangled.”

Observe that a correlation defined from a PME strategy is synchronous. [A converse to this statement is shown in Ref. 9, i.e., every synchronous strategy arises from (a convex combination of) PME strategies.] To see this, first recall Ando’s formula: for any X, Y, and ψHH of the form (7) with reduced density ρ, it holds that

ψXYψ=TrXρ1/2YTρ1/2,
(8)

where the transpose is taken with respect to the basis ui as in (7). Now, for a PME strategy S=(ψ,A) and any ν, write

δsync(S,ν)=1ExνaψAax(Aax)Tψ=1Exνaψ(Aax)2Idψ=1ExνaψAaxIdψ=0,

where the first equality is by definition, the second uses (8) together with the fact that for a PME strategy, the reduced density of ψ on either system is proportional to the identity and hence commutes with any operator, the third equality uses that all Aax are projections, and the last uses that they sum to identity.

We reproduce a definition from Ref. 16.

Definition 2.4
(local (ɛ, ν)-dilation). Given ɛ ≥ 0, a distribution ν on X×Y, and two strategies S=(ψ,A,B) and S̃=(ψ̃,Ã,B̃), we say that S̃ is a local (ɛ, ν)-dilation of S if there exists isometries VA:HAH̃AKA and VB:HBH̃BKB and a state auxKAKB such that
(VAVB)ψψ̃auxε,E(x,y)νa,b(VAVB)AaxBbyψÃaxB̃byψ̃aux21/2ε.

In Ref. 16, the second condition is required for all x, y, a, b. We require it to hold in an averaged sense only because this is more natural when seeking approximations that are independent of the size of the sets X,Y,A,B, as is the case in the context of this paper.

The following lemma implies that for any correlation CCq, there is a projective (but not necessarily maximally entangled) strategy that realizes it.

Lemma 2.5
(Naimark dilation). Letψbe a state inHAHB. LetA=Aaxbe a measurement onHAandB=Bbybe a measurement onHB. Then, there exists Hilbert spacesHAauxandHBaux, a stateauxHAauxHBaux, and two projective measurementsÂ=ÂaxandB̂=B̂byacting onHAHAauxandHBHBaux, respectively, such that the following is true. If we letψ̂=ψaux, then for allx, y, a, b,
ψAaxBbyψ=ψ̂ÂaxB̂byψ̂.
In addition,auxis a product state, meaning that we can write it asaux=auxAauxB, forauxAinHAauxandauxBinHBaux.

Definition 2.6.

A nonlocal game (or game for short) G is specified by a tuple (X,Y,A,B,ν,D) of finite question setsX and Y, finite answer setsA and B, a distribution ν on X×Y, and a decision predicateD:X×Y×A×B0,1 that we conventionally write as D(a, b|x, y) for (x,y)X×Y and (a,b)A×B. The game is symmetric if X=Y, A=B, ν(x, y) = ν(y, x) for all x,yX×Y, and for all a, b, x, y, D(a, b|x, y) = D(b, a|y, x). In this case, we write G=(X,A,ν,D). We often abuse notation and also use ν to denote the marginal distribution of ν on X.

Definition 2.7.
Given a game G=(X,Y,A,B,ν,D) and a strategy S=(ψ,A) in G, the success probability of S in G is
ω(G;S)=E(x,y)νa,bD(a,b|x,y)ψAaxBbyψ.

We show elementary and generally well-known lemmata that will be useful in the proofs. The first lemma relates two different measures of state-dependent distance between measurements on H.

Lemma 2.8.
Letγ, δ ≥ 0. LetHbe a Hilbert space andψHHbe a state. LetXbe a finite set, and for eachxX, letAaxaAbe a projective measurement andMaxaAbe an arbitrary measurement onH. Letμbe a distribution onX. Let
δ=1ExμaAψAax(Aax)Tψandγ=1ExμaAψAax(Max)Tψ.
(9)
Then,
(γδ)2ExμaAψIdAaxMax2ψ2γ+22δ.
(10)

Proof.
We start with the left inequality,
γ=1ExμaψAax(Max)Tψ=ExμaψAaxAaxMaxTψ+1ExμaψAax(Aax)TψExμaψIdAaxMax2ψ1/2Exμaψ(Aax)2Idψ1/2+δExμaψIdAaxMax2ψ1/2+δ,
where the first inequality is Cauchy–Schwarz and the last uses that for each xX, Aaxa is a measurement.
For the right inequality,
ExμaψIdAaxMax2ψ=ExμaψIdAax2+Max2ψ2RExμaψIdAaxMaxψ22R1γExμaψAaxIdIdAaxTIdMaxTψ2γ+2ExμaψAaxIdIdAaxT2ψ1/2ExμaψIdMaxT2ψ1/22γ+22δ,
where the first inequality uses that Aaxa and Maxa are measurements, the second uses the Cauchy–Schwarz inequality, and the last uses the definition of δ and that for each xX, Aax is a projective measurement and Maxa is a measurement.□

Given a density matrix ρ on H, define the canonical purification of ρ as the state

ψ=iλiuiui,

where ρ=iλiuiui is the spectral decomposition.

Lemma 2.9.
LetψHAHBandAaandBabe measurements onHAandHB, respectively. LetρAandρBbe the reduced density ofψonHAandHB, respectively. LetψAHAHAandψBHBHBbe the canonical purifications ofρAandρB, respectively. Then,
aψAaBaψaψAAaAaTψA1/2aψBBaBaTψB1/2.

Proof.
Let ψ=jλjujvj be the Schmidt decomposition. Let K=jλjujvj. Then,
aψAaBaψ=aTrAaKB̄aKaTrAaKKAaKK1/2aTrBāKKBāKK1/2,
where the inequality is Cauchy–Schwarz. Using that ρA = KK and ρB = KK, this concludes the proof.□

The next lemma gives conditions under which two strategies induce nearby correlations.

Lemma 2.10.
LetS=(ψ,A,B)be a strategy, letÂ=Âaxbe a family of POVM onHA, and letŜ=(ψ,Â,B). LetρAbe the reduced density ofψonHAandψAHAHAbe the canonical purification of it. LetSA=(ψA,A). Letνbe a distribution onX×Yandδ=δsync(SA;νA), whereνAis the marginal ofνonX. Let
γ=ExνAaTrAaxÂax2ρA.
LetCbe the correlation induced bySandĈbyŜ. Then,
Ex,yνa,b|Cx,y,a,bĈx,y,a,b|Oδ+γ.

Proof.
Conjugating Bby by a unitary if necessary, we assume without loss of generality that the reduced densities of ψ on either subsystem satisfy ρA = ρB. Then, ψA=ψ. As a first step in the proof, we show that
Ex,yνa,b|Cx,y,a,bψ(Aax)2Bbyψ|δ.
(11)
To show this, write
Ex,yνa,b|Cx,y,a,bψ(Aax)2Bbyψ|=Ex,yνa,bψAax(Aax)2BbyψExνAaψAax(Aax)2Idψ=1ExνAaψ(Aax)2Idψ,
(12)
where the first step uses that Aax(Aax)20 for all x, a, the second uses that bBby=Id for all y, and the third uses that aAax=Id for all x. Next, we observe that
1δ=ExνAaψAax(Aax)TψExνAaψ(Aax)2Idψ1/2ExνAaψId(Aax)T2ψ1/2=ExνAaTr(Aax)2ρA,
where the inequality on the second line is Cauchy–Schwarz and the last line uses our assumption that ρA = ρB. Plugging back into (12), this shows (11). For the second step, we show
Ex,yνa,b|ψAax2BbyψψÂax2Bbyψ|2γ.
(13)
To show (13), we first bound
Ex,yνa,b|ψAax2AaxÂaxBbyψ|Ex,yνa,b|ψAax2Bbyψ1/2Ex,yνa,b|ψAaxÂax2Bbyψ1/2,γ,
(14)
where the first inequality is Cauchy–Schwarz and the second bounds the first term by 1 and the second term by γ using bBby=aAax=1 and the definition of γ. An analogous calculation gives
Ex,yνa,b|ψAaxÂaxÂax2Bbyψ|γ.
(15)
Together, (14) and (15) give (13). Finally, the third step of the proof is given by the bound
Ex,yνa,b|Ĉx,y,a,bψÂax2Bbyψ|2γ+δ.
(16)
This is analogous to (11), except that we rely on an estimate for consistency δ̂ of the Âax. This can be obtained directly by using the left inequality of (10) in Lemma 2.8, which letting η=1ExaψAax(Âax)Tψ gives (ηδ)2γ so
ηγ+δ
(17)
and
1η=ExaψAaxÂaxTψExaψAaxAaxTψ1/2ExaψÂaxÂaxTψ1/2
using Lemma 2.9. Thus, (1δ)(1δ̂)(1η)2, which implies δ̂2η2γ by (17). Proceeding as for (11), this shows (16).

Combining (12), (13), and (16) proves the lemma.□

We introduce two simple lemmas originally due to Connes17 (who proved them in the much more general setting of semifinite von Neumann algebras). The lemmas allow one to provide estimates on ‖f(A) − g(B)‖F when A, B are Hermitian operators on H and f, g are real-valued functions. As discussed in the Introduction, these lemma were previously used in Ref. 7 to show a weaker result than we show here (which was sufficient for their purposes).

For λR, define χλ:RR by χλ(x) = 1 if xλ and 0 otherwise. Extend χλ to Hermitian operators on H using the spectral calculus. The first lemma appears as Lemma 5.6 in Ref. 7.

Lemma 2.11.
Letρbe a positive semidefinite operator on a finite-dimensional Hilbert space. Then,
0+χλρ1/2dλ=ρ,
where the integral is taken with respect to the Lebesgue measure onR+.

The second lemma appears as Lemma 5.5 in Ref. 7.

Lemma 2.12.
Letρ, σbe positive semidefinite operators on a finite-dimensional Hilbert space. Then,
0+χλρ1/2χλσ1/2F2dλσ1/2ρ1/2Fσ1/2+ρ1/2F.

The following result shows that an approximately consistent strategy is always close to a projective strategy. The result first appears in Ref. 18. The statement that we give here is taken from Ref. 14.

Proposition 2.13.
Let 0 ≤ δ ≤ 1. Letψbe a state onHHwhose reduced densities on either subsystem are identical. Letkbe an integer andQ1, …, Qkbe positive semidefinite operators onHsuch thatiQi = Id. Let
δ=1iψQiQiTψ.
Then, there exists orthogonal projectionsP1, …, PkonHsuch thatiPi = Id and
iψ(PiQi)2IdψOδ1/4.
(18)

The following is our main result. It states that a strategy that induces a correlation that is almost synchronous must be proportionately close, in a precise sense, to a projective maximally entangled strategy.

Theorem 3.1.

There are universal constantsc, C > 0 such that the following holds. LetXandAbe finite sets andν be a distribution onX. LetS=(ψ,A)be a symmetric strategy andδ=δsync(S;ν). Then, there is a measureμonR+and a family of Hilbert spacesHλHforλR+(both depending onψonly) such that the following holds. For everyλR+, there is a maximally entangled stateψλHλHλand for eachxa projective measurementAaλ,xonHλsuch that we have the following:

  1. Lettingρbe the reduced density ofψonHandρλbe the totally mixed state onHλH,
    ρ=λρλdλ.
    (19)
  2. Sλ=(ψλ,Aλ)provide an approximate decomposition ofSas a convex sum of projective maximally entangled (PME) strategies in the following sense:
    ExνaλTrAaxAaλ,x2ρλdμ(λ)Cδc.
    (20)

The key point in Theorem 3.1 is that the error estimates are independent of the dimension of H and of the size of the sets X and A. We remark that the integral over λ can be written as a finite convex sum. This is evident from the definition of ρλ as a multiple of the projection Pλ defined in (31). Since H is finite-dimensional, ρ has a discrete spectrum and Pλ takes on a finite set of values.

We note that the theorem does not imply that ψ itself is close to a maximally entangled state. Rather, (19) implies that after tracing an ancilla, which contains the index λ, this is the case. It is not hard to see that this is unavoidable by considering a game such that there exist multiple optimal strategies for the game that are not unitarily equivalent. For example, one can consider a linear system game that tests the group generated by the Pauli matrices σX, σZ and σY; this can be obtained from three copies of the Magic Square game as in, e.g., Ref. 19 (Appendix A). This game can be won with probability 1 using any state of the form

ψ=ϕ+A1B1ϕ+A2B2α00A3B3+β11A3B3,

where ϕ+ is an EPR pair (rank-2 maximally entangled state) and the measurement operators are block-diagonal with respect to the third system (i.e., X=XA1A200A3+XA1A211A3 for the first player). Crucially, the measurement operator’s dependence on the third system cannot be removed by a local unitary because the X′ and X components are not unitarily related. Although the strategy cannot be locally dilated to a maximally entangled strategy in the sense of Definition 2.4, it is not hard to see that it nevertheless has a decomposition of the form promised by Theorem 3.1.

Before turning to the proof, we give a pair of corollaries. The first shows that the conclusions of the theorem are maintained even without the assumption that S is symmetric.

Corollary 3.2.

LetS=(ψ,A,B)be a strategy. Letνbe a distribution onXandδ=δsync(S;ν). Then, the same conclusions as Theorem 3.1 hold (for different constantsc, C), whereρis chosen as the reduced density ofψon eitherHA(in which case the conclusions apply toAax) orHB(in which case they apply toBby).

Proof.
Using Lemma 2.9 and Jensen’s inequality, it follows that
ExνaψAaxBaxψ1δsync(SA;ν)1δsync(SB;ν),
where SA=(ψA,A) and SB=(ψB,B) with ψA and ψB being canonical purifications of the reduced density of ψ on HA and HB, respectively. This allows us to apply Theorem 3.1 separately to each symmetric strategy SA and SB to obtain the desired conclusions.□

The second corollary shows that the conclusions of the theorem imply an approximate decomposition of the correlation implied by S as a convex combination of synchronous correlations.

Corollary 3.3.
LetS=(ψ,A,B)be a projective strategy. Letνbe a distribution onX,δ=δsync(S;ν), andSλandμbe the family of strategies and the measure obtained from Theorem 3.1, respectively. LetC(respectively,Cλ) be the correlation induced byS(respectively,Sλ). Letν̃be any distribution onX×Xwith marginalν. Then,
E(x,y)ν̃a,bCx,y,a,bλCx,y,a,bλdλ=poly(δ).
(21)

The assumption that S is projective is without loss of generality since by Lemma 2.5 any correlation CCq(X,A) can be achieved by a projective strategy. By an averaging argument, the corollary immediately implies that for any game G with question distribution ν̃, there is a λ such that Sλ succeeds at least as well as S in G up to an additive loss poly(δ).

Proof.
Fix S, ν, ν̃, Sλ, and μ as in the statement of the corollary. Conjugating Bby by a unitary if necessary, we assume without loss of generality that the reduced densities of ψ on either subsystem are identical. For every λ, define a symmetric strategy S̃λ=(ψλ,A) and let C̃λ be the associated correlation. We first show that
E(x,y)ν̃a,b|Cx,y,a,bλC̃x,y,a,bλdλ|=poly(δ).
(22)
For this, we show that
Ex,ya,b|Cx,y,a,bTr(Aax)TBby(Aax)Tρ|=Oδ
(23)
and
λEx,ya,b|C̃x,y,a,bλTr(Aax)TBby(Aax)Tρλ|=Oδ.
(24)
Together with (19), combining (23) and (24) through the triangle inequality gives (22). To show (23), write using the triangle inequality
Ex,ya,b|Cx,y,a,bTrAaxTBbyAaxTρ|Ex,ya,b|ψIdAaxTAaxIdBbyIdAaxTψ|
(25)
+Ex,ya,bψIdAaxTBbyIdAaxTAaxIdψ|,
(26)
where we used the assumption that each Bby is a projection. Each of the two terms on the right-hand side is bounded in the same manner. We show how to bound the first,
Ex,ya,b|ψIdAaxTAaxIdBbyIdAaxTψ|Ex,ya,bψIdAaxTAaxIdBbyIdAaxTAaxIdψ1/2Ex,ya,bψIdAaxTBbyIdAaxTψ1/2ExaψIdAaxTAaxId2ψ1/212δ,
where the first inequality is Cauchy–Schwarz, the second uses aAax=b(Bby)2=Id, and the last follows by expanding the square and using the definition of δ. This bounds (25). Together with a similar bound for the term in (26), this shows (23). A similar proof shows (24).
Having established (22), we now prove
λE(x,y)ν̃a,b|C̃x,y,a,bλCx,y,a,bλ|dλ=poly(δ).
(27)
Combining (22) and (27) shows (21), concluding the proof. To show (27), we apply Lemma 2.10 for each λ to the strategy S=(ψλ,Aλ,B) here and  in Lemma 2.10 is A here. Since ψλ is maximally entangled and Aλ supported on its support, δ in Lemma 2.10 equals 0. Applying the lemma followed by Jensen’s inequality gives
λE(x,y)ν̃a,b|C̃x,y,a,bλCx,y,a,bλ|dλ=OλExaTrAaλ,xAax2ρλdλ1/2=poly(δ)
by (20). This shows (27) and concludes the proof.□

We now prove the theorem. As in the statement of Theorem 3.1, let S=(ψ,A) be a symmetric strategy. Let ρ be the reduced density of ψ on H. As a first step in the proof, we apply Proposition 2.13 to obtain a nearby symmetric projective strategy with nearly the same success probability.

Lemma 3.4.
There is a projective symmetric strategyS=(ψ,B)such that lettingδ=δsync(S,ν), thenδ′ = O(δ1/8) and
ExνaTr(AaxBax)2ρ=Oδ1/4.
(28)

Proof.
For each x, let δx=1aψAax(Aax)Tψ. By definition of δ, it holds that
δ=Exνδx.
(29)
For each xX, applying Proposition 2.13 to the measurement Aax gives a projective measurement Bax such that
aTr(AaxBax)2ρ=Oδx1/4.
Taking the expectation over x,
ExνaTr(AaxBax)2ρ=OExνδx1/4=OExνδx1/4=Oδ1/4,
(30)
where the second line uses Jensen’s inequality and the third uses (29). This gives (28). Let δ=δsync(S,ν). Then,
δδ=ExaψAax(Aax)TψψBax(Bax)Tψ=Exaψ(AaxBax)(Aax)Tψ+ψBax(AaxBax)TψExaTr(AaxBax)2ρ1/2ExaTr((Aax)2ρ)1/2+ExaTr((Bax)2ρ)1/2Oδ1/82,
where the second inequality follows from the Cauchy–Schwarz inequality and the last uses (30) to bound the first term and that for each x, Aaxa and Bax are measurements. This shows δ′ = O(δ1/8), as claimed.□

For every λR+, let

Pλ=χλ(ρ)
(31)

be the projection on the direct sum of all eigenspaces of ρ with the associated eigenvalue at least λ. Using Lemma 2.11, λTr(Pλ) = 1, so (λ) = Tr(Pλ) is a probability measure. Let Hλ be a Hilbert space of dimension, the rank of Pλ. We endow each Hλ with an orthonormal basis of eigenvectors of ρ that allows us to view Hλ as a subspace of Hλ for any λ′ ≤ λ, with Hλ=0 for any λ > ‖ρ‖ and the convention H0=H.

The next lemma shows a form of approximate commutation between Bax and Pλ.

Lemma 3.5.
The following holds:
λExνaBaxPλPλBaxF222δ,
(32)
whereδ′ = O(δ1/8) is as in Lemma 3.4.

Proof.
For convenience in the proof of the lemma, we identify the set A with Zm for some integer m. Define a family of unitaries Ubx indexed by xX and bA by
Ubx=ae2iπab/mBax.
(33)
With this definition, we observe that
ExEbUbxρ1/2ρ1/2UbxF2=22ExaTrBaxρ1/2Baxρ1/2=2δ,
(34)
where the expectation over x is taken with respect to the (marginal of) the game distribution ν, the expectation over b is uniform over Zm, the first equality uses the equality Ebe2(aa′)/m = δa,a (the Kronecker δ) for all a,aZm and the fact that for every x, Baxa is projective, and the second uses identity (8).
For each xX and bB, let σbx=(Ubx)ρUbx. Observe that for any λR+,
χλ(σbx)1/2=(Ubx)χλρ1/2Ubx.
Hence, using the definition (31) of Pλ,
ExEbλPλ(Ubx)PλUbxF2=ExEbλχλρ1/2χλ(σbx)1/2F2ExEbρ1/2(Ubx)ρ1/2UbxFρ1/2+(Ubx)ρ1/2UbxFExEbρ1/2(Ubx)ρ1/2UbxF21/2ExEbρ1/2+(Ubx)ρ1/2UbxF21/22δ4,
where the inequality on the second line follows from applying Lemma 2.12 independently for each x and b, the third line is the Cauchy–Schwarz inequality, and for the last inequality, the first term is bounded using (34) and the second term is bounded using ρ1/2F2=1. The claim follows since from definition (33), we get by expanding the left-hand side that for each x and λ,
EbUbxPλPλUbxF2=aBaxPλPλBaxF2.

With the preceding two lemmas in hand, we are ready to give the Proof of Theorem 3.1.

Proof of Theorem 3.1.

Fix a symmetric strategy S=(ψ,A) for G. Let Bax be the family of projective measurements obtained in Lemma 3.4, S=(ψ,B) and δ=δsync(S;ν).

For λR+, let Ãaλ,x=PλBaxPλ and ψλ denote the maximally entangled state on HλHλ. Then, S̃λ=(ψλ,Ãλ) is a well-defined symmetric strategy. Lemma 3.5 allows us to bound
λExa(BaxÃaλ,x)2PλF2dλ=λExaTrBaxPλBax(IdPλ)dλ=λExaTr[Bax,Pλ][Bax,Pλ]dλ=Oδ,
(35)
where for rewriting in the first and second lines, we used the definition of Ãaλ,x, the fact that Pλ is a projection for each λ, and that Bax is a projective measurement for all x and for the last line, we used (32).
It remains to turn the strategies S̃λ into projective strategies. For this, we apply Proposition 2.13 to each measurement Aaλ,xa for all x and λ. To justify this application, we evaluate
λExaψλÃaλ,xÃaλ,xψλdμ(λ)=λExaTrBaxPλBaxPλdλ=112λExaBaxPλPλBaxF2dλ1Oδ,
(36)
where the first equality uses the definition of (λ) and Ãaλ,x and (8), the second uses that Bax is projective, and the last line is by (32). For each x and λ, let Aaλ,x be the projective measurement that is associated with Ãaλ,x by Proposition 2.13. Using Jensen’s inequality and (36), the proposition gives the guarantee that
λExaTrAaλ,xÃaλ,x2Pλdλ=O(δ)1/8.
(37)
For each λ, the strategy Sλ=(ψλ,Aλ) is a PME strategy by definition, and (20) follows by combining (28), (35), and (37).□

We give two applications of Theorem 3.1. The first is to transferring “rigidity” statements obtained for PME strategies to the general case. The second is to the class of projection games.

As mentioned in the Introduction, Theorem 3.1 allows one to transfer rigidity statements shown for PME strategies to general strategies. We do not have a general all-purpose statement demonstrating this. Instead, we give two simple corollaries that are meant to describe sample applications. The first corollary considers a situation important in complexity theory, where one aims to show that a large family of measurements that constitute a successful strategy in a certain game must in some sense be consistent with a single larger measurement that “explains” it; see Subsection IV A 1. The second corollary considers a typical midpoint in a proof of rigidity, where one uses the game condition to derive certain algebraic relations on the measurements that constitute a successful strategy, which are then shown to impose a further structure; see Subsection IV A 2.

1. Application to showing classical soundness

Our first application arises in complexity theory when one is trying to show that quantum strategies in a certain nonlocal game obey a certain “global” structure. We first state the corollary and then describe a typical application of it.

Corollary 4.1.

LetG=(X,A,ν,D)be a symmetric game. Suppose given the following:

  • finite setsYandB,

  • a joint distributionponX×Y,

  • for every(x,y)X×Y, a functiongxy:A2B, the collection of subsets ofB, such that for any fixed (x, y), the setsgxy(a) foraAare pairwise disjoint, and

  • a convex monotone non-decreasing functionκ:[0,1]R+,

and suppose that given these data, the following statement holds:

  • For everyω ∈ [0, 1] and symmetric PME strategyS=(ψ,A)that succeeds with probabilityωinG, there is a family of measurementsMbyonH, indexed byyYand with outcomesbB, such that
    E(x,y)paψAaxM[gxy(a)]yψκ(ω),
    (38)
    whereM[gxy(a)]y=bgxy(a)Mby.

Then, the same statement extends to arbitrary symmetric projective strategiesS=(ψ,A), with the right-hand side in(38)replaced byκ(ω − poly(δ)) − poly(δ), whereδ=δsync(S;ν).

Note that using Lemma 2.8, the guarantee (38) can equivalently be expressed in terms of a state-dependent distance between Aax and Max=EypxM[gxy(a)]y, with px the conditional distribution p(x, ·)/p(x). The condition that the strategy S should be symmetric projective is very mild, as projectivity can always be obtained by applying Naimark dilation (Lemma 2.5) and symmetry is generally obtained as a consequence of symmetry in the game.

The loss in quality of approximation guaranteed by the corollary depends polynomially on δsync(S;ν). In many cases, this quantity can be bounded directly from a high success probability in the game. This is the case if, for example, the distribution ν is such that ν(x, x) ≥ (x) for some c > 0 and all x, where recalling that by slight abuse of notation, we use ν(·) to denote the marginal on either player. In this case, any strategy such that ωq(G;S)1ε has δsync(S;νA)ε/c and so no further assumption is necessary.

The assumption made in the proposition is typical of a rigidity result and is specifically meant to illustrate the potential applicability of our result to a setting such as that of the low-individual degree test of Ref. 14, which forces successful strategies in a certain game to necessarily have a specific “global” structure. For purposes of illustration, we state an over-simplified version of the main result from Ref. 14 result as follows:

Theorem 4.2
(Theorem 1.3 in Ref. 14, informal). Suppose that a symmetric strategyS=(ψ,A)succeeds in the “degree-dlow individual degree game”Gld, which hasX=FqmandA=Fq, with probability at least 1 − ɛ. Then, there exists a projective measurementG=Ggwhose outcomesgarem-variate polynomials overFqof individual degree at mostdsuch that
ExFqmaFqg:g(x)=aψAaxGgψ1poly(m)(poly(ε)+poly(d/q)).
(39)

To apply Corollary 4.1 to the setting of Theorem 4.2, let the game G in Corollary 4.1 be the “degree-d low individual degree game” Gld from Theorem 4.2. Let Y=y be a singleton and A be the set of m-variate polynomials over Fq of individual degree at most d. Let p be uniform over Fqm×Y. For every xFqm and aFq, let gxy(a) be the collection of polynomials that evaluate to a at x. Then, (39) gives (38) with κ(ω) = poly(m) · (poly(ɛ) + poly(d/q)), where ɛ = 1 − ω. To conclude, we note that for the specific game Gld, the condition ν(x, x) ≥ (x) for some c > 0 mentioned earlier holds, which allows us to bound δsync by O(ɛ).22 In conclusion, Corollary 4.1 shows that to prove Theorem 4.2, provided one is willing to accept a small loss in the approximation quality, it is sufficient to prove it for PME strategies. As observed in the Introduction, this allows for a significant simplification in the technical steps of the proof.

We give the proof of the corollary.

Proof of Corollary 4.1.
Fix a symmetric projective strategy S=(ψ,A) in G, and let ω denote its success probability. For each λR+, let Sλ=(ψλ,Aλ) be the PME strategy promised by Theorem 3.1 and ωλ be its probability of success in G. Let Mbλ,y be the family of measurements promised by the assumption of Corollary 4.1 such that
E(x,y)paψλAx,λM[gxy(a)]λ,yψλκ(ωλ).
Averaging with respect to the probability measure with density (λ) and using that κ is assumed to be convex monotone, it follows that
λEx,yaψλAax,λM[gxy(a)]λ,yψλdμ(λ)κλωλdμ(λ)κ(ω),
(40)
where ω′ = ω − poly(δ) by Corollary 3.3.

Claim 4.3.
The following holds:
λEx,yaψλAaxM[gxy(a)]λ,yψλdμ(λ)κ(ω)poly(δ).
(41)

Proof.
For any λR+, we have
|ψλAaxAax,λM[gxy(a)]λ,yψλ||ψλAaxAax,λAaxM[gxy(a)]λ,yψλ|+|ψλAax,λAaxAax,λM[gxy(a)]λ,yψλ|AaxAax,λIdψλAax,λIdψλ+AaxIdψλ,
(42)
where the first inequality uses that both Aax and Aaλ,x are projections and the second inequality uses M[gxy(a)]λ,y1 for all x, y and a. Averaging over λ,
λEx,yaψλAaxAaλ,xM[gxy(a)]λ,yψλdμ(λ)λExaAaxAax,λIdψλAax,λIdψλ+AaxIdψλdμ(λ)λExaAaxAax,λIdψλ2dμ(λ)1/2λExaAax,λIdψλ+AaxIdψλ2dμ(λ)1/2poly(δ),
where the first inequality uses (42), the second is the Cauchy–Schwarz inequality, and the last uses (20) to bound the first term, since for every λ, x, and a,
AaxAax,λIdψλ2=TrAaxAax,λ2ρλ.

For each y, b, define

Mby=ρ1/2λ1Tr(Pλ)PλMbλ,yPλdμ(λ)ρ1/2,

and note that Mby0 and

bMby=ρ1/2λ1Tr(λ)Pλdμ(λ)ρ1/2=Id
(43)

by (19). Thus, for each y, Mby is a valid measurement. Moreover, using (8), we get

Ex,yaψAaxM[gxy(a)]yψ=Ex,yaTrAaxρ1/2M[gxy(a)]yρ1/2=λEx,yaTrAaxPλM[gxy(a)]λ,yPλdλ=λEx,yaψλAaxM[gxy(a)]λ,yψλdμ(λ)κ(ω)poly(δ),

where the last inequality is by (41).□

2. Application to showing algebraic relations

Our second application concerns rigidity statements that go through algebraic relations, as is exemplified by the rigidity proofs for games such as the CHSH game, the magic square game, as well as more general classes of games; see, e.g., Ref. 20 for an exposition of this approach.

Corollary 4.4.

LetG=(X,A,ν,D)be a symmetric nonlocal game. Suppose that0,1X, and for any symmetric projective strategyS=(ψ,A)inG, forx0,1,A0x,A1xis a two-outcome measurement that can be represented as an observableAx=A0xA1x. Suppose that the following statement holds for some concave monotone non-decreasing functionκ:[0,1]R+.

For everyω ∈ [0, 1] and symmetric PME strategyS=(ψ,A)that succeeds with probabilityωinG, it holds that
TrA0A1A1A02ρκ(1ω).
(44)
Then, the same statement extends to arbitrary symmetric projective strategiesS=(ψ,A), with the right-hand side in(44)replaced byκ(ω + poly(δ)) + poly(δ), where
δ=maxδsync(S;q),δsync(S;ν),
(45)
withqbeing the uniform distribution on0,1Xandνbeing the marginal of the game distribution onX.

Since the aim of the corollary is to give a “toy” application of our results, we sketch the proof but omit the details.

Proof sketch.
Fix a symmetric projective strategy S=(ψ,A) in G, and let ω denote its success probability. For each λR+, let Sλ=(ψλ,Aλ) be the PME strategy promised by Theorem 3.1 and ωλ be its probability of success in G. Furthermore, let S̃λ=(ψλ,A). First, we claim that by an argument similar to the derivation of (22) in the proof of Corollary 3.3, it holds that
λδsyncS̃λ;qdλ=poly(δ),
(46)
where to show this, we use that the definition of δ in (45) involves measuring almost synchronicity under q. We may then achieve the desired conclusion as follows. First, we note that
TrA0A1A1A02ρ=λTrA0A1A1A02ρλdλ
(47)
by (19). Next, we use (46) to show
λTrA0A1A1A02ρλTrAλ,0Aλ,1Aλ,1Aλ,02ρλ=poly(δ),
(48)
where (20) is used, informally, to “switch” operators from one side of the tensor product to the other so that (46) can be applied to each operator in an expansion of the square in turn. Finally, the second term on the left-hand side in (48) is at most κ(ω − poly(δ)) using the assumption made in the corollary, Jensen’s inequality, and the fact that by Corollary 3.3, it holds that λωλω − poly(δ). This concludes the proof.□

Theorem 3.1 applies to almost consistent symmetric strategies. In this section, we give an example of how the results of the theorem can be applied to a family of games such that success in the game naturally implies a bound on consistency. This partially extends the main result in Ref. 21, with the caveat that our result applies only to projection games, and not the more general “weak projection games” considered in Ref. 21; it is not hard to see that this is necessary to obtain a “robust” result of the kind we obtain here.

Definition 4.5.

A game G=(X,Y,A,B,ν,D) is a projection game if for each (x,y)X×Y, there is fxy:AB such that D(a, b|x, y) = 0 if bfxy(a).

Theorem 4.6.
There are universal constantsc, C > 0 such that the following holds. LetG=(X,Y,A,B,ν,D)be a projection game andS=(ψ,A,B)be a strategy forGthat succeeds with probability 1 − ɛ, for some 0 ≤ ɛ ≤ 1. Then, there is a measureμonR+and a family of Hilbert spacesHλHAforλR+(both depending onψonly) such that the following holds. For everyλR+, there is a PME strategySλ=(ψλ,Aλ,B)forGsuch thatψλis a maximally entangled state onHλHλ, and moreover, ifωλis the success probability ofSλinG, then
λωλdμ(λ)1Cεc.
(49)

Proof.
Applying Naimark’s theorem (Lemma 2.5), extending ψ if necessary, we may assume that for every x, y, Aax and Bby are projective measurements. For each xX and aA, let
Bax=EyνxbD(a,b|x,y)Bby,
where for xX, νx is the conditional distribution of ν on Y, conditioned on x. The assumption that G is a projection game implies that for every x, aBaxId. Let ψA and ψB be the canonical purifications of the reduced density of ψ on HA and HB, respectively. Using Lemma 2.9,
1ε=ExaψAaxBaxψExaψAAax(Aax)TψA1/2ExaψBBax(Bax)TψB1/2,
which implies that
ExaψAAax(Aax)TψA(1ε)212ε.
(50)
Equation (50) shows that the symmetric projective strategy SA=(ψA,A) satisfies δsync(SA,ν)2ε. Thus, we can apply Theorem 3.1. Let μ, HλHA, and Aλ be as promised by the theorem. Since dim(HB)d, for each λ, we can find a purification ψλAB of ρλ = Pλ/Tr(Pλ) on HAHB; note that ψλAB is maximally entangled.
Next, we note that
ExaTrAaxBaxρλExaTrAaλ,xBaxρλdμ(λ)λExaTr(AaxAaλ,x)2ρλdμ(λ)1/2λExaTr(Bax)2ρλdμ(λ)1/2poly(ε),
(51)
where the first inequality is Cauchy–Schwarz and uses (19) and the second uses (50) to bound the first term by (20) and that for all x, aBaxId to bound the second by 1. Using that Aaλ,xρλ=ρλAaλ,x, since ρλ is totally mixed and Aaλ,x is supported on it, we have that
λExaTrAaλ,xBaxρλdμ(λ)=λExa1Tr(Pλ)TrAaλ,xPλBaxPλdμ(λ)=λExaψλAaλ,xBaxψλdμ(λ).
(52)
Equations (51) and (52) together give (49).□

I thank Laura Mančinska, William Slofstra, and Henry Yuen for comments and Vern Paulsen for pointing out typos in an earlier version. This work was supported by NSF CAREER Grant No. CCF-1553477, AFOSR YIP Award No. FA9550-16-1-0495, MURI Grant No. FA9550-18-1-0161, and the IQIM, an NSF Physics Frontiers Center (NSF Grant No. PHY-1125565) with support of the Gordon and Betty Moore Foundation (Grant No. GBMF-12500028).

The author has no conflicts of interest to disclose.

Data sharing is not applicable to this article as no new data were created or analyzed in this study.

1.
W.
Slofstra
, “
The set of quantum correlations is not closed
,”
Forum Math. Pi
7
,
E1
(
2019
).
2.
J. S.
Bell
, “
On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox
,”
Phys. Phys. Fiz.
1
(
3
),
195
(
1964
).
3.
N.
Brunner
,
D.
Cavalcanti
,
S.
Pironio
,
V.
Scarani
, and
S.
Wehner
, “
Bell nonlocality
,”
Rev. Mod. Phys.
86
(
2
),
419
(
2014
).
4.
B. S.
Tsirelson
, “
Some results and problems on quantum Bell-type inequalities
,”
Hadronic J. Suppl.
8
(
4
),
329
345
(
1993
).
5.
T.
Fritz
, “
Tsirelson’s problem and Kirchberg’s conjecture
,”
Rev. Math. Phys.
24
(
05
),
1250012
(
2012
).
6.
M.
Junge
,
M.
Navascues
,
C.
Palazuelos
,
D.
Perez-Garcia
,
V. B.
Scholz
, and
R. F.
Werner
, “
Connes’ embedding problem and Tsirelson’s problem
,”
J. Math. Phys.
52
(
1
),
012102
(
2011
).
7.
W.
Slofstra
and
T.
Vidick
, “
Entanglement in non-local games and the hyperlinear profile of groups
,”
Ann. Henri Poincare
19
,
2979
3005
(
2018
).
8.
L.
Mančinska
and
D. E.
Roberson
, “
Quantum isomorphism is equivalent to equality of homomorphism counts from planar graphs
,” in
2020 IEEE 61st Annual Symposium on Foundations of Computer Science (FOCS)
(
IEEE
,
2020
), pp.
661
672
.
9.
V. I.
Paulsen
,
S.
Severini
,
D.
Stahlke
,
I. G.
Todorov
, and
A.
Winter
, “
Estimating quantum chromatic numbers
,”
J. Funct. Anal.
270
(
6
),
2188
2222
(
2016
).
10.
L.
Mančinska
and
D.
Roberson
, “
Graph homomorphisms for quantum players
,” in
9th Conference on the Theory of Quantum Computation, Communication and Cryptography (TQC 2014)
(
Schloss Dagstuhl-Leibniz-Zentrum fuer Informatik
,
2014
).
11.
R.
Cleve
and
R.
Mittal
, “
Characterization of binary constraint system games
,” in
International Colloquium on Automata, Languages, and Programming
(
Springer
,
2014
), pp.
320
331
.
12.
S.-J.
Kim
,
V.
Paulsen
, and
C.
Schafhauser
, “
A synchronous game for binary constraint systems
,”
J. Math. Phys.
59
(
3
),
032201
(
2018
).
13.
T.
Vidick
and
S.
Wehner
, “
More nonlocality with less entanglement
,”
Phys. Rev. A
83
(
5
),
052310
(
2011
).
14.
Z.
Ji
,
A.
Natarajan
,
T.
Vidick
,
J.
Wright
, and
H.
Yuen
, “
Quantum soundness of the classical low individual degree test
,”
Quantum
6
,
614
(
2022
).
15.
Z.
Ji
,
A.
Natarajan
,
T.
Vidick
,
J.
Wright
, and
H.
Yuen
, “
MIP* = RE
,” arXiv:2001.04383 (
2020
).
16.
L.
Mančinska
,
J.
Prakash
, and
C.
Schafhauser
, “
Constant-sized robust self-tests for states and measurements of unbounded dimension
,” arXiv:2103.01729 (
2021
).
17.
A.
Connes
, “
Classification of injective factors cases II1, II, IIIλ, λ ≠ 1
,”
Ann. Math.
104
,
73
115
(
1976
).
18.
J.
Kempe
and
T.
Vidick
, “
Parallel repetition of entangled games
,” in
Proceedings of the Forty-Third Annual ACM Symposium on Theory of Computing
(
ACM
,
2011
), pp.
353
362
.
19.
A.
Coladangelo
,
A. B.
Grilo
,
S.
Jeffery
, and
T.
Vidick
, “
Verifier-on-a-leash: New schemes for verifiable delegated quantum computation, with quasilinear resources
,” in
Annual International Conference on the Theory and Applications of Cryptographic Techniques
(
Springer
,
2019
), pp.
247
277
.
20.
A.
Coladangelo
and
J.
Stark
, “
Robust self-testing for linear constraint system games
,” arXiv:1709.09267 (
2017
).
21.
L.
Mančinska
, “
Maximally entangled state in pseudo-telepathy games
,” in
Computing with New Resources
(
Springer
,
2014
), pp.
200
207
.
22.

In fact, for this game, c is only inverse polynomial in m, which still suffices, given the form of κ.