Given a complete orthocomplemented lattice L and a set S of nonnegative real functions on L, sufficient conditions are established that S should fulfill in order that L be atomic. The conditions are investigated under which L may be represented by the lattice of all closed subspaces of a separable Hilbert space. (As is well known, the atomicity of L plays an important role here.) Some unsolved problems are pointed out. In axiomatic quantum mechanics, the lattice L may represent the set of propositions whereas the set of functions S represents the set of physical states. The conditions imposed on the pair (L,S) then have a simple and plausible physical interpretation; an important condition imposed on (L,S) is the existence of the ``maximal'' (i.e., maximally determined) states which appear in the theory as limit constructions.

1.
J. M. Jauch, Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (Addison‐Wesley, Reading, Mass., 1968).
2.
V. S. Varadarajan, Geometry of Quantum Theory (Van Nostrand, Princeton, N. J., 1968), Vol. I.
3.
C.
Piron
,
Helv. Phys. Acta
37
,
439
(
1964
).
4.
J. M.
Jauch
and
C.
Piron
,
Helv. Phys. Acta
42
,
842
(
1969
).
5.
F. Jenč, to appear.
6.
R.
Haag
and
D.
Kastler
,
J. Math. Phys.
5
,
848
(
1964
).
7.
The following conventions are used in the rest of the paper. We denote the greatest lower bound by ∧, the least upper bound by ∨, and the complement of a by a′. 0 and 1 denote the least and greatest element of L, respectively. Orthogonality of two elements a,bεL,a⊥, means as usual as a≤b′. By probability measure on L we mean a nonnegative real function α on L with values in the interval [0,1], such that (i) α(0) = 0, (ii) α(l) = 1, and (iii) α(Viai) = Σiα(ai) if the elements ai are pairwise orthogonal (i = 1,2,…). As a filter F we denote a subset of a bounded lattice L, which satisfies the following conditions: (1) 0 is not an element of F; (2) a,bεF implies a∧bεF; (3) aεF implies xεF for any element x of L greater than a(≤x).
8.
G.
Emch
,
J. Math. Phys.
7
,
1413
(
1966
).
9.
All the necessary concepts and the theorems from general topology and the theory of linear topological vector spaces will be found in Refs. 10–14. Lattice theory is treated in Ref. 15.
10.
J. L. Kelley, General Topology (Van Nostrand, Princeton, N. J., 1955).
11.
N. Bourbaki, Elements de mathématique, Livre III. Topologie générate (Hermann, Paris, 1961), Chaps. 1, 2.
12.
E. Cech, Topological Spaces (Publish. House Czech. Acad. Sci., Prague, 1966).
13.
H. H. Schaefer, Topological Vector Spaces (Macmillan, New York, 1966).
14.
G. Köthe, Topological Linear Spaces. I (Springer, Berlin, 1969).
15.
L. Szász, Einfuhrung in die Verbandstheorie (Verlag Ungar. Akad. Wiss., Budapest, 1962).
16.
As will be seen in the proof of Theorem 1, this condition is true if every αεS is increasing on L [i.e., aεS,α≤b implies α(a)≤α(b)].
17.
The completion of L or S is defined only up to isomorphism13; let us denote the isomorphic images of L and S by L1 and S1, respectively. Then it is easy to see that a completely equivalent problem is obtained by taking for L1 the corresponding functional on l1 or S1 (i.e., taking on the same values on S1 as the functionals of L have on S).
18.
Since S is dense in in τ̄′, there exists, to any αεS̄, a generalized sequence,αdεS,αdd⃗α so that we have α(a) = a(α) = a(limdαd) = limdαd(a). Thus if every αεS is increasing on L, then every αεS̄ is increasing on L and, for as a≤b,α(a) = 1 implies α(b) = 1.
19.
J.
Gunson
,
Commun. Math. Phys.
6
,
262
(
1967
).
20.
The w*‐topology is the weak topology13,14 generated in the dual of B(H) by B(H). We have τp≤w*‐topology (i.e., τp is weaker than the w*‐topology).
21.
J. M.
Fell
,
Trans. Amer. Math. Soc.
94
,
365
(
1960
).
22.
This result is an easy consequence of Theorem I of Ref. 21.
23.
M. A. Neumark, Normierte Algebren (Deutscher Verlag der Wiss., Berlin, 1959): (a) p. 278;
(b) p. 277, Theorem 2, and p. 278, I;
(c) p. 305, Corollary of V;
(d) p. 64, I.
24.
H is the set of states in Segal’s sense (cf. Ref. 25).
25.
I. E. Segal, Mathematical Problems of Relativistic Physics (Benjamin, New York, 1963).
26.
J. Dixmier, Les algèbres d’operaleurs dans l’espace Hilberlien (Les algèbres de v. Neu mann) (Gauthier‐Villars, Paris, 1969);
(a) p. 48, Lemme 1;
(b) p. 51, Theoreme 1.
27.
J. W.
Calkin
,
Ann. Math.
42
,
839
(
1941
).
28.
J. C. T.
Pool
,
Commun. Math. Phys.
9
,
118
(
1968
).
29.
J. C. T. Pool, thesis (State University of Iowa, 1963) (Rept. No. SUI‐63, 17).
30.
The physical interpretation of (A) and (C) is clear: (A) mneans that for any proposition aεL there exists a state αεS̄ such that a is true in the state α. (C) means that if a implies b, then if a is true in the state αεS̄,b is true in the state α.
31.
Since, in the set of admissible states, a maximal state m is uniquely determined by the maximal set E1(m), the physical situation it describes cannot be further specified by any information. It seems worthwhile to remark that hypothesis (H) of Theorems 2 and 3 is a weakening of the postulate that, to any aεL, there exists a maximal pure state m with m(a) = 1. The latter postulate might be physically interpreted as follows: To any proposition aεL, there exists a set of propositions E1(m) (including a), which represents a maximal specification of a physical situation m of the system that cannot be further refined by any propositions concerning the system [the state m being uniquely determined31 by E1(m) and vice versa].
32.
N.
Zierler
,
Pacific J. Math.
11
,
1151
(
1961
):
(a) Lemma 1, 11; (b) Lemma 1, 12.
This content is only available via PDF.
You do not currently have access to this content.