Although physical laws or theories are often invoked in debates over “causality” and “determinism,” our best current understanding of physics assigns only a limited (though still very broad) validity to these concepts. It may be, thus, helpful (particularly when having to deal with the challenges posed by quantum mechanics) to think of them as prejudices, extrapolated from our experience with a limited (essentially classical) set of phenomena and/or theoretical models. This paper discusses how, over time, different physical theories have either reinforced or challenged these prejudices, focusing specifically on conservative “Laplacian” mechanics, dissipative mechanics (thermal physics), and quantum mechanics.
REFERENCES
1.
“Felix, qui potuit rerum cognoscere causas,” (“Fortunate, who was able to know the causes of things”), Virgil, Georgica (II, v. 490), has been taken to refer to Lucretius' work “De Rerum Natura” (“On the nature of things”).
2.
See, e.g.,
J. D.
Jackson
, Classical Electrodynamics
, 2nd ed. (
Wiley
,
Hoboken, NJ
, 1975
), Sec. 7.10.3.
M.
Pawłowski
,
T.
Paterek
,
D.
Kaszlikowski
,
V.
Scarani
,
A.
Winter
, and
M.
Żukowski
, “
Information causality as a physical principle
,” Nature
461
, 1101
–1104
(2009
).4.
D.
Pitalúa-García
, “
Quantum information causality
,” Phys. Rev. Lett.
110
, 210402
(2013
).5.
R.
Jones
, “
Resource Letter CD-1: Causality and determinism in physics
,” Am. J. Phys.
64
, 208–215
(1996
).6.
M.
Frisch
, “
Causation in physics
,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
, Spring 2022th ed., edited by
Edward N.
Zalta
(
Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University
,
Stanford, CA
, 2022
).7.
B.
Russell
, “
On the notion of cause
,” Proc. Aristotelian Soc.
13
, 1
–26
(1913
).8.
N.
Bohr
, “
On the notions of causality and complementarity
,” Science
111
, 51
–54
(1950
).9.
C.
Hoefer
, “
Causal determinism
,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
, Spring 2016th ed., edited by
Edward N.
Zalta
(
Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University
,
Stanford, CA
, 2016
).10.
J.
Earman
, “
Aspects of determinism in modern physics
,” in Handbook of the Philosophy of Science: Philosophy of Physics
, edited by
J.
Butterfield
and
J.
Earman
(
Elsevier
,
Amsterdam
, 2007
), pp. 1369
–1434
.11.
Earman's review (Ref. 10) is, in fact, a very good example of the strong association, in physics at least, of “determinism” with, essentially, differential equations. It covers many intriguing examples of non-unique or “pathological” solutions to problems in classical mechanics, classical field theories, and both special and general relativity. Unfortunately, I do not find this a very useful approach to the problem of determinism in quantum mechanics. Rather, to me, as I will try to make clear in Sec. V, the one-to-many relation between state vectors and measurement outcomes, as posited in the “orthodox” formalism and observed in actual experiments, is the very definition of indeterminism.
12.
Aristotle
, Physics, Book 2, Chap. 3, available online in the Internet Classics Archive: <http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.2.ii.html>13.
D.
Hume
, A Treatise of Human Nature, Book III, Sec. II, available online as part of the Project Gutenberg <https://www.gutenberg.org/files/4705/4705-h/4705-h.htm>14.
The emphasis on these kinds of causes and effects is a characteristic of mechanistic explanations of the world, which became widespread in the 17th century. See, for a historical perspective and many valuable insight,
D.
Dieks
, “
Mechanisms, explanation and understanding in physics
,” in Mechanistic Explanations in Physics and Beyond
, edited by
B.
Falkenburg
and
G.
Schiemann
(
Springer
,
Berlin
, 2019
), pp. 47
–64
.15.
It may seem that I am conflating here determinism and predictability, something which philosophers are always warning us not to do (Refs. 9 and 10). The question is subtle, but I believe it is certainly legitimate to ask for evidence from any model that calls itself deterministic before we lend it any credence. Otherwise, we might as well believe that everything that happens in the universe is determined by invisible causes of which we cannot know anything. Of course, we may want to cut our physical theories some slack: There may be many cases where exact prediction is an extremely challenging mathematical problem, but we otherwise have no reason to doubt the underlying model, because it has proved itself sufficiently (through verifiable predictions) elsewhere. On the other hand, an impossibility to come up with verifiable predictions in practice by a model that calls itself deterministic may also be an indication that this particular model has reached the limits of its applicability. This is, in my opinion, the case of so-called “deterministic chaos” the moment an accurate prediction requires the initial conditions to be specified to greater precision than allowed by quantum mechanics (see Sec. IV C).
16.
In fact, Newton's theory was criticized in his time by no less than Leibnitz and Huygens for not being “mechanistic” enough on this point! See S. Psillos and S. Ioannidis, “Mechanisms, Then and Now: From Metaphysics to Practice,” in the book cited in Ref. 14.
17.
According to Section 2 of Ref. 6, this has been used in philosophy to argue against the usefulness of the notion of cause itself. If so, this seems like backwards reasoning to me. The world as we experience it is time-asymmetric. If our notion of cause reflects this, and our physical theories do not, this is rightfully a problem for our physical theories, not the other way around.
18.
E.
Schliesser
and
T.
Demeter
, “
Hume's newtonianism and anti-Newtonianism
,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
, Summer 2020th ed., edited by
Edward N.
Zalta
(Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford, CA), see <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/hume-newton/>.19.
P. S.
de Laplace
, A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities
, translated into English from the original French 6th ed. by
F. W.
Truscott
and
F. L.
Emory
(
Dover Publications
,
Mineola, NY
, 1951
).20.
This reference, like the terms “Laplace's demon” and “Laplacian determinism,” has become standard, yet, interestingly, Earman (Ref. 10, p.
1388
) quotes a very similar statement made by Leibnitz over a century earlier.21.
F.
Del Santo
and
N.
Gisin
, “
Physics without determinism: Alternative interpretations of classical physics
,” Phys. Rev. A
100
, 062107
(2019
).22.
A.
Einstein
, “
On the movement of small particles suspended in stationary liquids required by the molecular-kinetic theory of heat
,” Ann. der Phys.
17
, 549
–560
(1905
), reprinted inA.
Einstein
, Investigations on the Theory of Brownian Movement
, edited by
R.
Fürth
, translated by A. D. Cowper (
Dover Publications
,
Mineola, NY
, 1956
). Also available online as part of the Collected Einstein Papers <https://einsteinpapers.press.princeton.edu/vol2-trans/137>23.
R.
Kubo
, “
The fluctuation-dissipation theorem
,” Rep. Prog. Phys.
29
, 255–284
(1966
).24.
R. P.
Feynman
,
R. B.
Leighton
, and
M.
Sands
, The Feynman Lectures on Physics
(
California Institute of Technology
,
Pasadena, CA
, 1967
), Vol.
I
, Sec. 39-4.25.
G. H.
Wannier
, Statistical Physics
, revised ed. (
Dover Publications
,
Mineola, NY
, 2010
), Chap. 18.26.
R. P.
Feynman
,
R. B.
Leighton
, and
M.
Sands
, The Feynman Lectures on Physics
(
Pearson Education
,
India
, 1964
), Vol.
I
, Secs. 40-6 and 41-2.27.
S. H.
Strogatz
, Nonlinear Dynamics and Chaos: With Applications to Physics, Biology, Chemistry, and Engineering
(
Westview Press
,
Boulder, CO
, 2014
).28.
W. H.
Zurek
, “
Decoherence, chaos, quantum-classical correspondence, and the algorithmic arrow of time
,” Phys. Scr. T
76
, 186
–198
(1998
).29.
A.
Einstein
, “
On the quantum theory of radiation
,” originally published in Phys. Z.
18
, 121
(1917
);reprinted in
Sources of Quantum Mechanics
, edited by
B. L.
van der Waerden
, Classics of Science, Vol.
5
(
Dover
,
Mineola, NY
, 1968
).30.
A.
Einstein
,
B.
Podolsky
, and
N.
Rosen
, “
Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete?
,” Phys. Rev.
47
, 777
–780
(1935
).31.
The comprehensive article review article by
F.
Laloë
, “
Do we really understand quantum mechanics? Strange correlations, paradoxes, and theorems
,” Am. J. Phys.
69
, 655–701
(2001
) covers a number of alternative “interpretations” (many of which are actually extensions, and, as such, really different physical theories) of quantum mechanics. Note that most of them are, at best, only indirectly concerned with questions of causality or determinism: in most cases, their primary purpose is to address questions like the ontological status of the wavefunction, or to make sense of the collapse postulate.32.
In a class by itself is the Everettian, or “many-worlds” interpretation, which does not involve hidden variables. This interpretation, in effect, embraces the indeterminism implied by the one-to-many correspondence between quantum states and possible outcomes, by asserting that every single possible outcome is actually realized in one of a multitude of “worlds” that come into being whenever a system in a state such as Eq. (6) is “observed.” (Depending on the interpretation, these may be either true physical or purely “mental” worlds.) As these worlds are, by assumption, inaccessible to each other, this, the only truly deterministic prediction of the theory, is neither verifiable nor disprovable. Within the single-world perspective that is the only one available to any observer, it remains a fact that identically prepared systems will yield different, unpredictable results, for which no causal explanation is given.
33.
A. M.
Gleason
, “
Measures on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space
,” J. Math. Mech.
6
, 885
–893
(1957
), see http://www.jstor.org/stable/24900629.34.
J. S.
Bell
, “
On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox
,” Physics (N.Y.)
1
, 195
–200
(1964
).35.
S.
Kochen
and
E. P.
Specker
, “
The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics
,” J. Math. Mech.
17
, 59
–87
(1967
), see https://www.jstor.org/stable/24902153.36.
For a very accessible presentation of some of these results, see
N. D.
Mermin
, “
Hidden variables and the two theorems of John Bell
,” Rev. Mod. Phys.
65
, 803
–815
(1993
).37.
In practice, however, experiments to check the predictions of Bell's theorems (Ref. 36) have been carried out on simpler kinds of entangled states, such as a superposition of states of polarization, H and V (for horizontal or vertical) of two photons, of the form
, or a superposition of the states of two atoms of the form
.
38.
C. J.
Wood
and
R. W.
Spekkens
, “
The lesson of causal discovery algorithms for quantum correlations: Causal explanations of Bell-inequality violations require fine-tuning
,” New J. Phys.
17
, 033002
(2015
).39.
This, of course, does not make these correlations any less mysterious! In a recent paper, Spekkens and co-workers have argued for what they call “Quantum Causal Models” as a possible way to deal with them:
J.-M.
Allen
,
J.
Barrett
,
D. C.
Horsman
,
C. M.
Lee
, and
R. W.
Spekkens
, “
Quantum common causes and quantum causal models
,” Phys. Rev. X
7
, 031021
(2017
).40.
L. D.
Landau
and
E. M.
Lifshitz
, Statistical Physics
, 3rd ed. (
Pergamon Press
,
Oxford
, 1980
).41.
D.
Drahi
,
N.
Walk
,
M. J.
Hoban
,
A. K.
Fedorov
,
R.
Shakhovoy
,
A.
Feimov
,
Y.
Kurochkin
,
W. S.
Kolthammer
,
J.
Nunn
,
J.
Barrett
, and
I. A.
Walmsley
, “
Certified quantum random numbers from untrusted light
,” Phys. Rev. X
10
, 041048
(2020
).42.
H. J.
Briegel
, “
On creative machines and the physical origins of freedom
,” Sci. Rep.
2
, 522
(2012
).43.
LIGO Scientific Collaboration and Virgo Collaboration
, “
Observation of gravitational waves from a binary black hole merger
,” Phys. Rev. Lett.
116
, 061102
(2016
).44.
The general question of “mechanistic” explanations in science is currently the subject of an active debate. According to the article cited in Ref. 16, this includes proposals to expand the concept of “mechanism” to make it essentially synonymous with “causal pathways.”
45.
See
N. D.
Mermin
, “
Making better sense of quantum mechanics
,” Rep. Prog. Phys.
82
, 012002
(2019
), Sec. 3.3.3: “When I act on the world, the action I take is my free choice. Reciprocally, when the world acts back on me in response to my action, quantum mechanics can tell me nothing more than the probability of the response I can expect: the world's reaction to my action is the world's free choice.” While this was written from the perspective of one specific interpretation of quantum mechanics (QBism), it may be taken to apply in the “standard” (Copenhagen) interpretation as well.© 2022 Author(s). Published under an exclusive license by American Association of Physics Teachers.
2022
Author(s)
AAPT members receive access to the American Journal of Physics and The Physics Teacher as a member benefit. To learn more about this member benefit and becoming an AAPT member, visit the Joining AAPT page.