The alternative pilot-wave theory of quantum phenomena—associated especially with Louis de Broglie, David Bohm, and John Bell—reproduces the statistical predictions of ordinary quantum mechanics but without recourse to special ad hoc axioms pertaining to measurement. That (and how) it does so is relatively straightforward to understand in the case of position measurements and, more generally, measurements, whose outcome is ultimately registered by the position of a pointer. Despite a widespread belief to the contrary among physicists, the theory can also account successfully for phenomena involving spin. The main goal of this paper is to explain how the pilot-wave theory's account of spin works. Along the way, we provide illuminating comparisons between the orthodox and pilot-wave accounts of spin and address some puzzles about how the pilot-wave theory relates to the important theorems of Kochen and Specker and Bell.

1.
T.
Norsen
, “
The pilot-wave perspective on scattering and tunneling
,”
Am. J. Phys.
81
(
4
),
258
266
(
2013
).
2.
S.
Goldstein
,
D.
Dürr
, and
N.
Zanghí
, “
Quantum equilibrium and the origin of absolute uncertainty
,”
J. Stat. Phys.
67
,
843
907
(
1992
).
3.
Note that here, in discussing the measurement from the point of view of orthodox QM, the word “particle” is used in an extended sense—meaning, for example, “an electron.” Of course, according to orthodox QM, an electron is not literally a particle in the sense of being a point-like object following a definite trajectory. Whereas, according to the pilot-wave theory, a single electron comprises both a quantum wave and a (literal) particle. Readers are hereafter assumed to be able to judge, from the context, in which sense the word “particle” is used.
4.
W.
Pauli
, “
Über den Zusammenhang des Abschlusses der Elektronengruppen im Atom mit der Komplexstruktur der Spektren
,”
Z. Phys.
31
,
765
783
(
1925
).
5.
See, for example, Lubos Motl, “
David Bohm born 90 years ago
,” <http://motls.blogspot.com/2007/12/david-bohm-born-90-years-ago.html>.
6.
S.
Kochen
and
E.
Specker
, “
The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics
,”
J. Math. Mech.
17
,
59
87
(
1967
).
7.
N. D.
Mermin
, “
Hidden variables and the two theorems of John Bell
,”
Rev. Mod. Phys.
65
(
3
),
803
815
(
1993
).
8.
D.
Bohm
,
R.
Schiller
, and
J.
Tiomno
, “
A causal interpretation of the Pauli equation (A)
,”
Suppl. Nuovo Cimento
1
,
48
66
(
1955
);
see also
T.
Takabayasi
, “
The vector representation of spinning particle in the quantum theory, I
,”
Prog. Theor. Phys.
14
,
283
302
(
1955
).
9.
See, e.g.,
C.
Dewdney
,
P. R.
Holland
, and
A.
Kyprianidis
, “
What happens in a spin measurement
,”
Phys. Lett. A
119
,
259
267
(
1986
);
C.
Dewdney
,
P. R.
Holland
, and
A.
Kyprianidis
, “
A causal account of non-local Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen spin correlations
,”
J. Phys. A
20
,
4717
4732
(
1987
).
10.
J. S.
Bell
, “
Introduction to the hidden variable question
,”
Proceedings of the International School of Physics ‘Enrico Fermi,’ Course IL: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics
(
Academic
,
New York
,
1971
), pp.
171
181
.
A somewhat more detailed elaboration can be found in
J. S.
Bell
, “
Quantum mechanics for cosmologists
,” in
Quantum Gravity 2
, edited by
C.
Isham
,
R.
Penrose
, and
D.
Sciama
(
Clarendon Press
,
Oxford
,
1981
), pp.
611
637
.
Both essays are reprinted in
J. S.
Bell
,
Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics
, 2nd ed. (
Cambridge U.P.
,
Cambridge
,
2004
).
11.
W.
Gerlach
and
O.
Stern
, “
Der experimentelle Nachweis der Richtungsquantelung im Magnetfeld
,”
Z. Phys.
9
,
349
352
(
1922
).
12.

Note that this expression for the field is simplified and idealized: A more precise expression would involve field components perpendicular to ẑ—which would allow the divergence of B to vanish, as it of course should—as well as a large constant field in the z-direction. As it is usually explained, this large constant field causes rapid precession about the z-axis: This makes any transverse forces (that would otherwise arise from the transverse magnetic field gradients) average to zero. It is much simpler, though, to simply look the other way in regard to the violation of Maxwell's equations, and thus avoid needing to talk about any of these subtleties, by simply pretending that Eq. (6) accurately describes the field to which the particles are subjected.

13.

If the reflected wave term from Eq. (14) is retained, the detailed particle trajectories are a little more complicated. During the time period when the incident and reflected packets overlap, the particle velocity in that (y < 0) overlap region is slightly oscillatory, with an average velocity—in precisely, the sense explained and used in the earlier paper—that is slightly less than k/m by an amount proportional to (κz)2. Thus, particles very near the trailing edge of the incident packet will in fact be overtaken by the trailing edge of the packet before reaching y = 0 and will hence be swept away, back out to the left, by the reflected packet. In short, particles that happen to begin in a small (parabolic) slice near the trailing edge of the incident packet will not behave as described in the main text, but will instead reflect. The behavior of the particles that do transmit through to the y > 0 region, however, is (in the applicable κw0 limit) unaffected. So we will continue to suppress discussion at this level of detail in the main text.

14.
D.
Bohm
and
B.
Hiley
,
The Undivided Universe
(
Routledge
,
London
,
1993
), pp.
73
78
.
15.
Actually there is one subtle point that deserves to be addressed. In analyzing the measurement of z-spin, we have assumed that the incident wave packet has an essentially rectangular cross-sectional profile, with (as mentioned explicitly) some width w along the z-direction and (as only really assumed tacitly) some width w′ along the x-direction. This makes the problem “effectively 2D” in the sense that (for the width-w′ range of x-values where the wave function has support and where the particle might therefore be) nothing depends on x. If, however, the incident wave function is the same but the SG apparatus is rotated through some arbitrary angle (not an integer multiple of 90°), this nice symmetry is spoiled. Everything still works as claimed; it's just that one has to think a little bit (about, e.g., slicing the 3D wave packet up into a stack of planes perpendicular to n̂) to convince oneself of this. Alternatively, one can recognize that the statistics of the measurement outcomes will not depend on the exact cross-sectional profile of the incident packet and hence imagine that the cross-sectional profile of the incident packet is rotated in tandem with the SG device so that the analysis remains transparent.
16.

Of course, the mere fact that the two sub-beams are spatially separated is not sufficient to prove that the empty packet is forevermore dynamically irrelevant to the motion of the particle. The “empty” spin-down sub-beam could be made to become dynamically relevant, for example, by arranging (by use, say, of appropriate magnetic fields) to deflect the spin-down beam back up toward the spin-up beam, at which point interference effects—including perhaps the re-constitution of a guiding wave proportional to (10)—could occur. But if, as suggested in Fig. 4, the spin-down sub-beam is blocked by a brick wall, then the usual process of decoherence will render it impossible, at least for all practical purposes, to arrange the appropriate overlapping of the two components of the wave function, and treating the wave as having “effectively collapsed” is entirely warranted.

17.
This particular illustration of the “
contextuality” of spin (for the pilot-wave theory) is due
, in essence, to David Z. Albert: see
Quantum Mechanics and Experience
(
Harvard U.P.
,
Cambridge, MA
,
1994
), pp.
153
155
.
18.
J. S.
Bell
, “
On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics
,”
Rev. Mod. Phys.
38
,
447
452
(
1966
), reprinted in Bell (2004), Ref. 10.
19.
N.
Bohr
, “
Discussions with Einstein on epistemological problems in atomic physics
,” in
Albert Einstein: Philosopher Scientist
, edited by
P. A.
Schillp
(
Library of Living Philosophers
,
Evanston, Illinois
,
1949
).
20.
A.
Shimony
, “
Contextual hidden variables theories and Bell's inequalities
,”
Brit. J. Phil. Sci.
35
(
1
),
25
45
(
1984
).
21.
We assume here that Δ>w so that the two sub-beams downstream of the SG device do not overlap spatially.
22.
T.
Norsen
, “
The theory of (Exclusively) local beables
,”
Found. Phys.
40
,
1858
1884
(
2010
).
23.

It is perhaps worth noting explicitly that the non-locality cannot be used for signaling: if a large ensemble of pairs are prepared in the state (39), and Alice chooses at the last minute whether to subject all of the particles on her side to an SGz measurement, or some other spin measurement, or no measurement, Bob will see the same 50/50 statistics on his side regardless of her choice.

24.
J. S.
Bell
, “
On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox
,”
Physics
1
(
3
),
195
200
(
1964
), reprinted in Bell (2004), Ref. 10.
For a detailed analysis, see
S.
Goldstein
,
T.
Norsen
,
D.
Tausk
, and
N.
Zanghí
, “
Bell's theorem
,”
Scholarpedia
6
(
10
),
8378
200
, <http://www.scholarpedia.org/article/Bell's_theorem>.
25.
M.
Daumer
,
D.
Dürr
,
S.
Goldstein
, and
N.
Zanghí
, “
Naive Realism about Operators
Erkenntnis
45
,
379
397
(
1996
).
26.
The authors of Ref. 25 describe themselves as following Bell in concluding that, for the pilot-wave theory, “spin is not real.” Bell, for example, writes (in the first essay of Ref. 10): “We have here a picture in which although the wave has two components, the particle has only position. The particle does not ‘spin,’ although the experimental phenomena associated with spin are reproduced. Thus the picture resulting from a hidden-variable account of quantum mechanics need not very much resemble the traditional classical picture that the researcher may, secretly, have been keeping in mind. The electron need not turn out to be a small spinning yellow sphere.” Gestures in the direction of this same point were made even earlier by
M.
Renninger
, “
Zum Wellen-Korpuskel-Dualismus
,”
Z. Phys.
136
,
251
261
(
1953
),
translated by
W.
De Baere
as “
On Wave-Particle Duality
,” <http://arxiv.org/abs/physics/0504043>; and still earlier by Lorentz, who discussed in 1922 a pilot-wave theory of photons, previously suggested by Einstein;
see
H. A.
Lorentz
,
Problems of Modern Physics
(
Dover
,
New York
,
1967
), p.
157
.
27.
D.
Dürr
,
S.
Goldstein
, and
N.
Zanghí
, “
Quantum equilibrium and the role of operators as observables in quantum theory
,”
J. Stat. Phys.
116
,
959
1055
(
2004
).
Reprinted as Chapter 3 of
D.
Dürr
,
S.
Goldstein
, and
N.
Zanghí
,
Quantum Physics Without Quantum Philosophy
(
Springer-Verlag
,
Berlin
,
2013
).
28.
J. S.
Bell
, “
Beables for quantum field theory
,” preprint CERN-TH 4035/84 (1984), reprinted in Bell (
2004
), Ref. 10.
29.
J. S.
Bell
, “
Against ‘Measurement
,’” in
62 Years of Uncertainty
, edited by
A. I.
Miller
(
Plenum
,
New York
,
1990
), reprinted in Bell (2004), Ref. 10.
30.
See, for example,
P.
Holland
,
The Quantum Theory of Motion
(
Cambridge U.P.
,
Cambridge
,
1993
), Chap. 9;
C.
Dewdney
,
P.
Holland
, and
A.
Kyprianidis
,
op cit.
(
1987
);
D.
Bohm
and
B.
Hiley
,
The Undivided Universe
(
Routledge
,
London
,
1993
), Chap. 10;
C.
Dewdney
, “
Constraints on quantum hidden-variables and the Bohm theory
,”
J. Phys. A
25
,
3615
3626
(
1992
).
31.
J. S.
Townsend
,
A Modern Approach to Quantum Mechanics
, 2nd ed. (
University Science Books
,
Mill Valley, CA
,
2012
). All quotes are from Chaps. 3 and 4.
32.
For example, in
D.
Griffiths
,
Introduction to Electrodynamics
, 2nd ed. (
Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs
,
NJ
,
1989
), the author writes: “
all magnetic fields are due to electric charges in motion, and in fact, if you could examine a piece of magnetic material on an atomic scale you would find tiny currents: electrons orbiting around nuclei and electrons spinning on their axes
.”
And later: “
Since every electron constitutes a magnetic dipole (picture it, if you wish, as a tiny spinning sphere of charge), you might expect paramagnetism to be a universal phenomenon
.”
Interestingly, Griffiths is more carefully orthodox about spin in his Introduction to Quantum Mechanics
, 2nd ed. (
Pearson Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River
,
NJ
,
2004
).
33.

In this respect it is somewhat telling that the worst offenses against the official orthodox view tend to occur in figures and illustrations. Almost all quantum mechanics textbooks, for example, include diagrams depicting the precession, induced by the presence of a magnetic field, of a particle's spin vector about some axis. Townsend's text (Ref. 31) avoids that particular misleading suggestion of a classical picture. But his front cover art—depicting a Stern-Gerlach spin measurement much like our Fig. 1—includes little circles with arrows (pointing, respectively, up and down) in the downstream sub-beams. The circles are even yellow, inviting us to recall Bell's warning, quoted earlier in Ref. 26 note.

AAPT members receive access to the American Journal of Physics and The Physics Teacher as a member benefit. To learn more about this member benefit and becoming an AAPT member, visit the Joining AAPT page.